Skip to main content

Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 18))

Abstract

This chapter considers the relationship between the concepts and conceptions of law and the rule of law. It begins by arguing that the ideal embedded in the concept of the rule of law cannot be logically derived from merely combining the content of the concept rule with the content of the concept law. The rule of law has content that transcends both the atomic concepts of rule and law of which the more complex concept is constructed, as well as the formal assertion that law rules, regardless of its relationship to certain principles, including both negative and positive liberties. In that sense, it reconsiders the relationship not only between the rule of law and concept of freedom by recalling the distinction between two concepts of liberty but also between the rule of law and constitutional democracy. Finally, it concludes by suggesting that the tendency to reduce the democratic principle to the majority rule (or majority principle), i.e. to whatever pleases the majority, as part of the positive liberty, is contrary both to the negative liberty and to the rule of law itself.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Vid. v.gr. MacCormick (2007, 2): “Law taken in this sense [i.e. as an institutional normative order] is obviously a central important feature of states as such and, in particular, of constitutionalist states or ‘law-states’.”

  2. 2.

    Vid. v.gr. MacCormick (2007, 3): “This [i.e. the distinction between politics and public Law] has much to do with sustaining the character of a state as a law-state. (‘Law-state’ is here used to refer to a state-under-law, or a constitutionalist state, in which the exercise of power is subjected to effective constitutional constraints and the rule of law obtains, it is equivalent to the German term ‘Rechtsstaat’.)”

  3. 3.

    Since we consider that RoL is equivalent to SoL, as we will insist in the following part, hereinafter we will refer explicitly to RoL, but mutatis mutando it applies implicitly to SoL.

  4. 4.

    At the end of the day it seems to be a false dilemma: we must be governed both by the best laws (reason) and by the best human beings (passion). It is in the case of an actual or eventual conflict between them that the laws and reasons ought to prevail over human beings and passion.

  5. 5.

    It is worth pointing out that we agree with Atienza that the (good) legislator must begin by using clear and precise language to avoid problems related to ambiguities and vagueness (R1) and must carry on by inquiring about the coherency and completeness of the legal system to avoid contradictions and gaps (R2). However, we are at variance with him in the order of the pragmatic and teleological rationalities, and hence, have inverted their places. Our explanation is simple: the legislator must continue by drafting at least one end (R3) into law, but it may be the case of establishing more than two ends – or sets of interests, purposes or values – (R4) and not the other way around. Finally, the legislator must guarantee an overall justified principle embedded into the law or at least not violated by it (R5).

    By the same token, the (good) adjudicator must begin by asking about the clarity and precision of the language used (R1); and, only when the language is neither clear nor precise, must carry on by inquiring about the coherency and completeness of the legal system (R2). Analogously, only when the language and legal system appear to be incoherent or incomplete, the adjudicator must go on to request an end (R3), as in the case when there are more than two ends – or sets of interests, purposes or values – equally available, by appealing to the better one (R4). Finally, only when their consequences and effects are illegitimate, the adjudicator must strive to secure an overall legitimate principle (R5).

  6. 6.

    Although this adage and its twin Fiat iusticia, ruat cælum (“Let justice be done, even if heavens falls”) have analogous meanings along the lines of “justice must be done at any price or regardless of consequences.” Nowadays, the former – popularized by the Emperor Ferdinand I – is used to criticize a legal opinion or practice that wants to preserve maxims in law at any price despite absurd or contradictory consequences, whereas the latter – recognized by William Murray, Lord Mansfield – is used to eulogize the realization of justice despite appearing to be outweighed by a pragmatic or utilitarian consideration: “The constitution does not allow reasons of state to influence our judgments: God forbid it should! We must not regard political consequences; however formidable soever they might be: if rebellion was the certain consequence, we are bound to say ‘fiat iustitia, ruat cælum’ (Let justice be done even if the heaven falls).” (Mansfield 1770, 2561–2.)

  7. 7.

    In fact, the existence of the Senate was designed to divide the most dangerous branch of government and to give stability to the government by protecting the minorities against a speedy and unreflected legislative majority in the House of Representatives.

References

  • Aristotle. 1988. Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1999. Nicomachean ethics. Trans. T. Irwin, Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, M. 1989a. Sociología jurídica y ciencia de la legislación. In El derecho y sus realidades. Investigación y enseñanza de la sociología jurídica, ed. R. Bergalli. Barcelona: PPU.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, M. 1989b. Contribución a la teoría de la legislación. Doxa 6: 385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, M. 1990. Para una teoría de la argumentación jurídica. Doxa 8: 39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, M. 1997. Contribución a la teoría de la legislación. Madrid: Tecnos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. 1832. The province of jurisprudence determined and the uses of the study of jurisprudence, ed. J. Austin Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. 1969. Four essays on liberty, ed. I. Berlin Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio, N. 1971. Le bon législateur. In Le raisonnment juridique/Legal reasoning/Die jurisdiche argumentation, ed. H. Hubien. Bruxelles: Établissements Émile Bruylant.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodenheimer, E. 1962. Jurisprudence. The philosophy and method of the law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, M.T. 1929. On the commonwealth. Trans. G.H. Sabine and S.B. Smith. Columbus: The Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coke, E. 1607. Prohibitions del Roy. In The selected writings of Sir Edward Coke, vol. I, ed. S. Sheppard. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coke, E. 1608. Calvin’s case, or the case of the postnati. In The selected writings of Sir Edward Coke, vol. I, ed. S. Sheppard. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Confucius (2002), Analects. Trans. James Legge. Available at Project Gutenberg Etext, The Chinese Classics (Confucian Analects).

    Google Scholar 

  • Constant, B. 1820. Collection complète des ouvrages. París: Béchet Libraire.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1978. Taking rights seriously, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1985. A matter of principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1996. Freedom’s law. The moral reading of the American constitution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Sovereign virtue. The theory and practice of equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 2006. Is democracy possible here? Principles for a new political debate. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 2011. Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2002. In the dark side of the conventionality thesis? In Studies in social, political and legal philosophy. Philosophy of law and of politics, ed. E. Villanueva. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2004. Assessing democracy and rule of law: Access to justice. In Proceedings of the 21st IVR world congress, Lund (Sweden), 12–17 August, 2003, Part I: Justice, ed. A. Peczenik. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2005. The quest for legisprudence: Constitutionalism v. Legalism. In The theory and practice of legislation: Essays on legisprudence, ed. L.J. Wintgens. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2007. Legisprudence: The forms and limits of legislation. Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoría del Derecho 1: 247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2008. The living tree: Fixity and flexibility. A general theory of (judicial review in a) constitutional democracy? Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoría del Derecho 2: 285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2009a. The living tree constitutionalism: Fixity and flexibility. Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoría del Derecho 3: 37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2009b. Legisprudence: The role and rationality of legislators – vis-à-vis judges – towards the realization of justice. Mexican Law Review 1(2): 91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, I.B. 2010. Ronald Dworkin’s Justice for hedgehogs and partnership conception of democracy (with a comment to Jeremy Waldron’s “A majority in the lifeboat”). Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoría del Derecho 4: 65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L.L. 1958. Positivism and fidelity to law –A reply to professor Hart. Harvard Law Review 71: 630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L.L. 1968. The anatomy of law. New York: Frederick A. Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L.L. 1969. The morality of law, 2nd ed. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L.L. 1999. The case of the speluncean explorers. Harvard Law Review 112: 1851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guinier, L. 1994. The tyranny of the majority. Fundamental fairness in representative democracy. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, A. 1985. Speech, June 18, 1787. In Selected writings and speeches of Alexander Hamilton, ed. M.J. Frisch. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1958. Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard Law Review 71: 593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The concept of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1994. The concept of law, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1960. The constitution of liberty. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, O.W. 1917. Southern Pacific v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. 1945. General theory of law and state. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. 1967. Pure theory of law, 2nd ed. Trans. M. Knight, Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. 2002. Introduction to the problems of legal theory. Trans. B. Litschewski-Paulson and S.L. Paulson. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lincoln, A. 1990. New birth of freedom. The Gettysburg address, November 19, 1863. In Lincoln on democracy, ed. M.M. Cuomo and H. Holzer. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1999. Questioning sovereignty: Law, state and nation in the European commonwealth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 2007. Institutions of law. An essay in legal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madison, J. 1961. No. 51. In The federalist papers, ed. C. Rossiter. New York: Mentor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansfield, W.M. 1770. R v. Wilkes, 4 Burr 2527 [98 ER 327].

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, J. 1824. Osborn v. Bank of United States, 22 U.S. 738.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1958. Considerations on representative government. Indianapolis: Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1989. On liberty. In On liberty and other writings, ed. S. Collini. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia, A. 1989. The rule of law as a law of rules. University of Chicago Law Review 56: 1187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 1992. Inequality reexamined. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville, A. 1969. Democracy in America. New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. 2002. Large legislatures. In Legal and political philosophy. Philosophy of law and of politics, ed. E. Villanueva. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. 2008. The concept and the rule of law. Georgia Law Review 43: 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waluchow, W.J. 2007. A common law theory of judicial review. The living tree. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Imer B. Flores .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Flores, I.B. (2013). Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy). In: Flores, I., Himma, K. (eds) Law, Liberty, and the Rule of Law. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 18. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4743-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics