Skip to main content

The Rule of Law, Validity Criteria, and Judicial Supremacy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Law, Liberty, and the Rule of Law

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 18))

Abstract

The concept of the rule of law and the ideals expressing its content are deeply contested. Theorists distinguish two broad conceptions: procedural rule of law and substantive rule of law. The former focuses largely on the procedures by which law is enacted and applied while the latter focuses on the content of the law. One might argue that both conceptions are somehow part of the very concept of law, but this much is clear: whether internal to law or not, the standards comprising the rule of law, procedural and substantive, are also standards of political legitimacy. This chapter analysis those elements of the U.S. rule of recognition dealing with constitutional interpretation and judicial supremacy in order to evaluate them under procedural rule of law standards; as these elements are increasingly common among other legal systems, the conclusions drawn here will be applicable to these other legal systems. But while judicial supremacy seems to violate procedural rule of law standards, which are also standards of political legitimacy, it does not follow that judicial supremacy is politically illegitimate. The analysis here is concerned with just one element that contributes to political legitimacy; no assumption is made, though, satisfaction of procedural rule of law standards is a necessary condition of legitimacy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    118 U.S. 425 (1886). For a defence of this view, vid. Alexander and Schauer (1997). For its part, the Court has not always adhered to this view. Vid. U.S. v. U.S. Coin and Currency, 401 U.S. 715 (1971), 741.

  2. 2.

    Kramer argues that the Supreme Court has usurped final authority, which should be taken back by the people. In any event, the descriptive claim, grounded in a comprehensive historical analysis, confirms that the official practice today confers final authority over the Constitution to the Supreme Court; the normative claim is that this is illegitimate. But the normative issue is not relevant for a positivist analysis of the content of the rule of recognition – although it is undeniably important.

  3. 3.

    Hodgson v. Minnesota, 497 U.S. 417 (1990), 480 (dissenting).

  4. 4.

    So far I have focused on Supreme Court declarations that a law is unconstitutional; however, additional issues are raised by Court declarations that a law is constitutional. But it is important to be careful here. Just as a Court decision that one of the Justices believes mistaken does not preclude that Justice from dissenting the next time the issue comes up or require the Justice to change his or her vote, so too it does not require any official to enforce a law that he or she believes, contra the Supreme Court ruling, is unconstitutional. While as Frank Easterbrook points out, there is a longstanding practice among presidents to refuse to enforce statutes that they believe to be unconstitutional, there might very well be a practice among officials, including presidents, not to enforce statutes they believe the Court has mistakenly declared to be constitutional. On this vid. Easterbrook (1989–1990) and Paulsen (1994, 267 et seq.).

  5. 5.

    Arizona v. Evans, 514 U.S. 1 (1995), 8–9.

  6. 6.

    Of course, many theorists believe that, as a matter of political morality, the Court ought not to have this authority. Vid. v.gr. Waldron (1999).

  7. 7.

    Here it is important to remember that the notion of legitimacy is a moral notion that is concerned with the extent to which the state is morally justified in using its coercive force.

  8. 8.

    505 U.S. 833.

  9. 9.

    505 U.S. 866.

  10. 10.

    505 U.S. 999.

References

  • Adler, M.C., and M.D. Dorf. 2003. Constitution existence conditions and judicial review. Virginia Law Review 89: 1105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, L., and F. Schauer. 1997. On extrajudicial interpretation. Harvard Law Review 110: 1359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, W.J. 1986. Speech. In The great debate: Interpreting our written constitution, ed. W.J. Brennan. Washington, DC: Federalist Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1977. Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterbrook, F.H. 1989–1990. Presidential review. Case Western Law Review 40: 905.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J.C. 1924. The nature and source of law. New York: The MacMillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenawalt, K. 2009. How to understand the rule of recognition and the American constitution. In The rule of recognition and the U.S. constitution, ed. K.H. Himma and M.C. Adler. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1994. The concept of law, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, L. 2005. The people themselves: Popular constitutionalism and judicial review. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiter, B. 2001. Legal realism and legal positivism reconsidered. Ethics 111: 278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paulsen, M.S. 1994. The most dangerous branch: Executive power to say what the law is. Georgetown Law Journal 83: 217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia, A. 1997. A matter of interpretation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. 1999. Law and disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kenneth Einar Himma .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Himma, K.E. (2013). The Rule of Law, Validity Criteria, and Judicial Supremacy. In: Flores, I., Himma, K. (eds) Law, Liberty, and the Rule of Law. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 18. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4743-2_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics