Skip to main content

Why Precedent in Law (and Elsewhere) Is Not Totally (or Even Substantially) About Analogy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Legal Argumentation Theory: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 102))

Abstract

Cognitive scientists and others who conduct research on analogical reasoning often claim that the use of precedent in law and elsewhere is an application of reasoning by analogy. In fact, however, law’s principle of precedent, as well as the way in which precedent is used in ordinary argument, is quite different. The typical use of analogy in legal argument, including the use of analogies to earlier decisions, involves the retrieval of a source analog (or exemplar) from multiple candidates in order to help make the best decision now. But the legal principle of precedent requires that a prior decision be treated as binding, even if the current decision maker disagrees with that decision. When the identity between a prior decision and the current question is obvious and inescapable, precedent thus imposes a constraint quite different from the effect of a typical argument by analogy. The importance of drawing this distinction between analogy and precedent is not so much in showing that a common claim in the psychological and cognitive science literature is mistaken, but that making decisions under the constraints of binding precedent is itself an important form of decision deserving to be researched in its own right, but which has been ignored because of the erroneous conflation of constraint by precedent with reasoning by analogy.

This chapter first appeared in Perspectives on Psychological Science, vol. 3 (2008), pp. 454–460.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “There is no word which is used more loosely, or in a greater variety of senses, than Analogy” (Mill 1861).

  2. 2.

    Technically, the obligation of a court to follow previous decisions of the same court is referred to as stare decisis (“stand by what has been decided”), and the more encompassing term precedent is used to refer both to stare decisis and the obligation of a lower court to follow decisions of a higher one. What I say here applies to both kinds of precedent, although stare decisis is to many non-lawyers more counter-intuitive.

  3. 3.

    Of course it is often the case that the precedent case or event or decision is consistent with what the decision-maker now wishes to do. In such instances, however, the existence of the precedent actually has no effect. Only when the existence of a precedent constrains a decision-maker to do what she would otherwise not do does the precedent in fact make a difference, and that is what distinguishes a precedent as make-weight from a precedent that has some causal effect on the decision.

References

  • Alexander, L. 1989. Constrained by precedent. Southern California Law Review 63: 1–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, L., and E. Sherwin. 2001. The rule of rules: Morality, rules, and the dilemmas of law. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashley, K.D. 1990. Modeling legal arguments: Reasoning with cases and hypotheticals. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanchette, I., and K. Dunbar. 2000. Analogy use in naturalistic settings: The place of audience, emotion and goals. Memory and Cognition 29: 330–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, S. 1996. Exemplary reasoning: Semantics, pragmatics, and the rational force of legal argument. Harvard Law Review 109: 923–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, A.L. 1989. Analogical learning and transfer: What develops? In Similarity and analogical reasoning, ed. S. Vosniadou and A. Ortony, 396–412. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnet v. Coronado Oil. & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 406 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting). Editorial – Justice Denied. 2007. New York Times, July 5, 2007, p. 12

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards v. Arizona. 1981. 451 U.S. 477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsworth, P. 2005. Legal reasoning. In The Cambridge handbook of thinking and reasoning, ed. K.J. Holyoak and R.G. Morison, 685–704. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbus, K.D. 2001. Exploring analogy in the large. In The analogical mind: Perspectives from cognitive science, ed. D. Gentner, K.J. Holyoak, and B.N. Kokinov, 23–58. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbus, K.D., D. Gentner, A.B. Markman, and R.W. Ferguson. 1998. Analogy just looks like high level perception: Why a domain general approach to analogical mapping is right. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 10: 231–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D. 1983. Structure mapping: A theoretical framework for analogy. Cognitive Science 7: 155–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D., M.J. Rattermann, and K.D. Forbus. 1993. The role of similarity in transfer: Separating retrievability from inferential soundness. Cognitive Psychology 25: 524–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gick, M.L., and K.J. Holyoak. 1980. Analogical problem solving. Cognitive Psychology 12:306–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gick, M.L., and K.J. Holyoak. 1983. Schema induction and analogical transfer. Cognitive Psychology 15: 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griswold v. Connecticut. 1965. 381 U.S. 479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D.R. 1995. A review of mental leaps: Analogy in creative thought. AI Magazine, Fall 1995: 75–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D.R. 2001. Analogy as the core of cognition. In The analogical mind: Perspectives from cognitive science, ed. D. Gentner, K.J. Holyoak, and B.N. Kokinov, 499–538. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K.J. 1982. An analogical framework for literary interpretation. Poetics 11: 105–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K.J. 2005. Analogy. In The Cambridge handbook of thinking and reasoning, ed. K.J. Holyoak and R.G. Morison, 117–142. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K.J., and K. Koh. 1987. Surface and structural similarity in analogical transfer. Memory and Cognition 15: 323–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K.J., and D. Simon. 1999. Bidirectional reasoning in decision making by constraint satisfaction. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 128: 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K.J., and P. Thagard. 1995. Mental leaps: Analogy in creative thought. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K.J., and P. Thagard. 1997. The analogical mind. American Psychologist 52: 35–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K.J., D. Gentner, and B.N. Kokinov. 2001. Introduction: The place of analogy in cognition. In The analogical mind: Perspectives from cognitive science, ed. D. Gentner, K.J. Holyoak, and B.N. Kokinov, 1–19. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, E. 2006. Expertise, talent, and social encouragement. In The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance, ed. K.A. Ericsson, N. Charness, P.J. Feltovich, and R.R. Hoffman, 31–40. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, D. 1997. Reason is too large: Analogy and precedent in law. Emory Law Journal 50: 1197–1243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Judicial Business of the United States Courts (Administrative Office of the United States Courts), Table S-3. 2005. http://www.uscourts.gov/judbus2005/tables/s3.pdf

  • Khong, Y.F. 1992. Analogies at war: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu, and the Vietnam decisions of 1965. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kokinov, B.N., and R.M. French. 2003. Computational models of analogy-making. In Encyclopedia of cognitive science, vol. 1, ed. L. Nadel, 113–118. London: Nature Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamond, G. 2006. Precedent and analogy in legal reasoning. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2006/entries/legal-reas-prec/.

  • Levi, E. 1949. Introduction to legal reasoning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1861. Considerations on representative government. In J.M. Robson (Ed.), Collected works of John Stuart Mill, 29, 371–577 (1963). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miranda v. Arizona. 1966. 384 U.S. 436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulsen, M.S. 2005. The intrinsically corrupting influence of precedent. Constitutional Commentary 22: 289–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R.A. 2008. How judges think. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ring v. Arizona. 2002. 536 U.S. 584, 613 (Kennedy, J., concurring).

    Google Scholar 

  • Roe v. Griffits. 1766. 98 Eng. Rep. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roe v. Wade. 1973. 410 U.S. 113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. 1987. Precedent. Stanford Law Review 39: 571–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, J., and H. Spaeth. 1996. The influence of stare decisis on the votes of Supreme Court justices. American Journal of Political Science 40: 971–1004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D., D.C. Krawczyk, and K.J. Holyoak. 2004. Construction of preferences by constraint satisfaction. Psychological Science 15: 331–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spellman, B.A. 2004. Reflections of a recovering lawyer: How becoming a cognitive psychologist – and (in particular) studying analogical and causal reasoning – changed my views about the field of law and psychology. Chicago-Kent Law Review 79: 1187–1214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spellman, B.A., and K.J. Holyoak. 1992. If Saddam is Hitler then who is George Bush?: Analogical mapping between systems of social roles. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 62: 913–933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spellman, B.A., and K.J. Holyoak. 1996. Pragmatics in analogical mapping. Cognitive Psychology 31: 307–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spiro, R.J., P.J. Feltovich, R.L. Coulson, and D.K. Anderson. 1989. Multiple analogies for complex concepts: Antidotes for analogy-induced misconception in advanced knowledge acquisition. In Similarity and analogical reasoning, ed. S. Vosniadou and A. Ortony, 498–531. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K.E., and R.E. West. 2000. Individual differences in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23: 645–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C.R. 1993. On analogical reasoning. Harvard Law Review 106: 741–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, P.E. 1999. Theory driven reasoning about possible pasts and probable futures: Are we prisoners of our perceptions? American Journal of Political Science 43: 335–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • United States ex rel. Fong Foo v. Shaughnessy, 234 F.2d 715 (2d Cir. 1955).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wasserstrom, R. 1961. The judicial decision: Toward a theory of legal justification. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinreb, L.L. 2005. Legal reason: The use of analogy in legal argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper emerged out of a series of illuminating conversations and exchanges with Dan Simon and Barbara Spellman, and I thank both of them for serving as involuntary foils and for extensive comments on an earlier draft. Larry Alexander, Michelle Cowley, and David Lynch also provided helpful comments, and Henry Monaghan, Matt Stephenson, Carol Steiker, Bill Stuntz, Larry Tribe, Mark Tushnet, and Lloyd Weinreb furnished useful legal references. Research support was provided by the Harvard Law School, the Joan Shorenstein Center on the Press, Politics and Public Policy, Harvard University, and the University of Oxford.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frederick Schauer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schauer, F. (2013). Why Precedent in Law (and Elsewhere) Is Not Totally (or Even Substantially) About Analogy. In: Dahlman, C., Feteris, E. (eds) Legal Argumentation Theory: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 102. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4670-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics