Skip to main content

Information, Negation, and Paraconsistency

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 26))

Abstract

This paper begins by arguing that a truth conditional approach to the semantics for relevant logic is unnatural. Rather, we should adopt an informational semantics. On this view, the indices in the model theory are not possible or impossible worlds, but are situations. A statement is not true or false at a situation; rather a situation can be said either to contain or fail to contain certain pieces of information. Valid inference, then, is seen as information preservation, not truth preservation. The distinction between truth and information gives us some freedom in our treatment of logic. For example, we may have a very classical theory of truth but a very non-classical theory of information. On the other hand, we may accept very non-classical theories of truth (such as dialetheism) together with an informational treatment of logic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Well, this isn’t strictly speaking true. Some relevant logicians, especially Meyer and Restall, include the so-called Church constant T in their language. This constant is true at every index in every model.

  2. 2.

    See Barwise and Perry (1983). The suggestion of the link between relevant logic and situation semantics was first made by John Perry (in Barwise and Perry 1985 and in conversation with me in 1992) and Barwise (1993). Their ideas have been developed in Restall (1996), Beall and Restall (2006) and Mares (19962004).

  3. 3.

    Quoted in Seligman and Moss (1997, p. 288).

  4. 4.

    I still used the notion of truth conditions in Mares (2004), but laid the foundations for the informational interpretation there. I made my real informational turn in Mares (2009).

  5. 5.

    I have developed a position since I wrote this paper. See Mares (2010).

  6. 6.

    The incompatibility (or sometimes “compatibility”) interpretation of negation was brought into relevant logic by Dunn (1993), but was originally formulated by Goldblatt (1974) in the context of orthologic (a generalisation of quantum logic).

  7. 7.

    I am grateful to Mark Colyvan for pressing me on this point.

  8. 8.

    This is a simplification of William James’ view.

  9. 9.

    I am grateful to Greg Restall for forcefully arguing that we need not interpret the little grey men classically even if we adopt a classical theory of truth.

  10. 10.

    He made a similar reply in conversation. I’m not sure I have his reply exactly right, so I do not attribute it to him.

  11. 11.

    Of course this is not an argument against Priest since he does not subscribe to an informational reading of his semantics. My point is only that on the informational approach to semantics it is not clear that we have to accept the T-scheme even if we have a naive theory of truth.

  12. 12.

    Using ‘second order’ in the sense in which it is used in the vagueness literature, i.e. as in ’second order vagueness’.

  13. 13.

    I have only looked at the treatment of negation here. For the other connectives, see Mares (2004200920122010).

References

  • Barwise, J. 1993. Constraints, channels, and the flow of information. In Situation theory and its applications, vol 3, ed. P. Aczel, Y. Katagiri, and S. Peters. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., and J. Perry. 1983. Situations and attitudes. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., and J. Perry. 1985. Shifting situations and shaken attitudes. Linguisitics and Philosophy 8: 105–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J.C., and G. Restall. 2006. Logical pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J.M. 1993. Star and perp: Two treatments of negation. Philosophical Perspectives 7: 331–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. 2004. Information. In The blackwell guide to philosophy of computing and information, ed. L. Floridi. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldblatt, R. 1974. Semantical analysis of orthologic. Journal of Philosophical Logic 3: 19–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E.D. 1996. Relevant logic and the theory of information. Synthese 109: 345–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E.D. 2004. Relevant logic: A philosophical interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E.D. 2009. General information in relevant logic. Synthese 167: 343–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E.D. 2010. The nature of information: A relevant approach. Synthese 175 Supplement, 1: 111–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E.D. 2012. Relevance and conjunction. Journal of Logic and Computation, 22: 7–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. 1992. What is a non-normal world? Logique et analyse 35: 291–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. 2000. Motivations for paraconsistency: The slippery slope from classical logic to dialetheism. In Frontiers of paraconsistent logic, ed. D. Batens, C. Mortensen, G. Priest, and J.-P. van Bendigem. Baldock: Research Studies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. 2008. Introduction to non-classical logic: From ifs to is. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. 1995. Four-valued semantics for relevant logics (and some of their Rivals). Journal of Philosophical Logic 24: 139–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. 1996. Information flow and relevant logic. In Logic, language, and computation, vol 1, ed. J. Seligman and D. Westerståhl. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, J., and L.S. Moss. 1997. Situation theory. In Handbook of logic and language, ed. J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. 2006. Vagueness in context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edwin D. Mares .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mares, E.D. (2013). Information, Negation, and Paraconsistency. In: Tanaka, K., Berto, F., Mares, E., Paoli, F. (eds) Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 26. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4438-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics