Skip to main content

The Ritual Dimension of Law: Normality, Normativity, and Critique

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Self-sufficiency of Law

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 99))

  • 1037 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter reinforces the conclusions reached in Chap. 9 about law’s being a special venue by arguing that law possesses a ritual nature, which sparks off two opposite but inseparable dimensions. On the one hand, there is a ‘nondiscursive’ dimension where ‘normative facts’ are produced, which are able to set stable standards of normality for social reality. On the other hand, there is a ‘discursive’ dimension, in which social subjects can question and revise these very same normative facts. On account of this two-dimensional structure, social subjects within the legal field can renegotiate, rephrase, and reframe their social surroundings. In this regard, these dimensions (the one conservative and the other transformative) are both opposed and deeply intertwined. The nondiscursive dimension promotes the establishment of a shared context of action – the legal field – in which social subjects are compelled to adopt a given stock of knowledge and categories, which cannot be questioned from inside the legal field. This context of action is safeguarded by its own ritual character. At the very same time, the discursive dimension permits and even prompts social subjects to question and criticise accepted social definitions, meanings, rules, roles, precisely by capitalising on the nondiscursive structure of law. The chapter also examines the notion of ritual, its role in social life, and its relationship to law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See supra, 7.4.

  2. 2.

    In the field of legal studies, few works are specifically devoted to examining the relation between ritual and law. Among them, Chase (2005), Garapon (2010), and Winn (1992). As it will become clear, my understanding of ritual and of its relation to law is quite different from theirs. Therefore, though very useful, I will not consider these works in this chapter.

  3. 3.

    According to many, this is a straightforward dysfunction (see Danet 1980, 451–452).

  4. 4.

    Berger and Luckmann (1967, 92) define the question of plausibility as “the subjective recognition of an overall sense ‘behind’ the situationally predominant but only partial institutionalized motives of one’s own as well as of one’s fellowmen”. In other words, it relates to a ‘horizontal’ level of integration, connected to “the total institutional order to several individuals participating in it in several roles, or to several partial institutional processes in which a single individual may participate at any given time”.

  5. 5.

    I would briefly like to remark that the solution advanced by Berger and Luckmann is not persuasive. They contend that, once people start to lose their memory of the actual way institutions have shaped up, the production of knowledge is meant to postulate and legitimise the existence of a symbolic universe, which is presented as the source of each and every institution. In this view, knowledge is seen as a form of narrative instrumental in the legitimation of the institutional order. Such a narrative, Berger and Luckmann believe, is rather more likely to be accepted by successive generations, as they are not aware of the concrete problematic circumstances in which institutions have originally emerged. All communities develop knowledge as a set of conceptual machineries of universe-maintenance, which safeguard the borders of their symbolic universe. In my opinion, Berger and Luckmann overemphasise the legitimising role of the various systems of knowledge (more or less specialised) that they mention: mythology, theology, therapy, philosophy, and science are deemed to be nothing but gears of a complex universe-maintenance machinery. These forms of knowledge are thought of as merely designed to offer a comprehensive justification for the whole institutional order, in order for all institutions to be understood as necessary parts of a fully integrated totality.

  6. 6.

    I will mainly draw on Rappaport (1999) and Seligman et al. (2008). See also Rosati (2008).

  7. 7.

    See for instance Bell (2009 b), 164; Seligman et al. (2008), 5.

  8. 8.

    See also Rosati (2008), Chap. 3.

  9. 9.

    For a much closer analysis of these characteristics, see Rappaport (1999), Chap. 2.

  10. 10.

    It is important to note, however, that this does not concern the propositional or locutionary component of ritual acts, i.e. the content of what is being said or done. Rather, the unquestionability relates to the performative one, that is, to the way it is said or done. For example, in the speech act: “This Court decrees that the decision appealed should be nullified”, the annulment is supposed to be based on arguments and proofs. The content of the decision can be criticised and revised precisely like the performative component of an ordinary speech act in normal life can be. In contrast, the performative component, “This Court decrees”, cannot be questioned as if an ordinary speaker said to another speaker “I order”. In the case of an ordinary speech act, the performative element raises a claim of rightness that can be questioned and thus must be redeemed by advancing convincing arguments. As I will say shortly, in the case of a ritual speech act, the performative element must already-and-always be accepted by the very same participation in the ritual. In a trial, participants take for granted that “The Court decrees” is an unquestionable formula meant to confirm performatively the already-and-always accepted authority of the Court.

  11. 11.

    See supra, Chap. 3.

  12. 12.

    On the notion of normality and its role in social life, see Croce and Salvatore (2012), Chap. 2. On the potential risks tied to Schmitt’s institutional theory, see Croce and Salvatore (2007) and Croce (2011a).

  13. 13.

    This is the label used in Croce and Salvatore (2012) in order to signify Schmitt’s institutional theory.

  14. 14.

    See supra, 9.4.

  15. 15.

    As Danet (1980, 498) observes, everything can be questioned with the exception of the legal frame itself: “What parties and witnesses do and say is questionable, but what those who control the dispute process do and say is not”.

  16. 16.

    As Mather and Yngvesson (1980, 793) remark, “[t]he official legal language prescribes the general frameworks and definitions to be used in classifying events in a dispute, but the actual use of those categories will depend upon the intermediary legal specialists”.

References

  • Austin, J.L. 1962. How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, C. 2009a. Ritual theory, ritual practice, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, C. 2009b. Rituals: Perspectives and dimensions, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellah, R.N. 2005. Durkheim and ritual. In The Cambridge companion to Durkheim, ed. J.C. Alexander and P. Smith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, P.L., and T. Luckmann. 1966. The social construction of reality: A treatise in the sociology of knowledge. New York: Anchor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chase, O.G. 2005. Law, culture, and ritual. Disputing systems in cross-cultural context. New York/London: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Croce, M. 2011a. Does legal institutionalism rule out legal pluralism? Schmitt’s institutional theory and the problem of the concrete order. Utrecht Law Review 7(2): 42–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Croce, M., and A. Salvatore. 2007. Ethical substance and the coexistence of normative orders. Carl Schmitt, Santi Romano, and Critical Institutionalism. Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law 56: 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Croce, M., and A. Salvatore. 2012. The legal theory of Carl Schmitt. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danet, B. 1980. Language in the legal process. Law and Society Review 14(3): 445–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Carolis, M. 2008. Il paradosso antropologico. Nicchie, micro mondi e dissociazione psichica. Macerata: Quodlibet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garapon, A. 2010. Bien juger. Essai sur le rituel judiciaire. Paris: Odile Jacob.

    Google Scholar 

  • Llewellyn, K.N. 1940. The normative, the legal and the law-jobs: The problem of juristic method. Yale Law Journal 49(8): 1355–1400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mather, L., and B. Yngvesson. 1980. Language, audience, and the transformation of disputes. Law and Society Review 15(3–4): 775–821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menski, W. 2010. Sanskrit law: Excavating vedic legal pluralism. In SOAS school of law legal studies research paper, no. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mortati, C. 1967. Istituzioni di diritto pubblico. Padova: CEDAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rappaport, R. 1999. Ritual and religion in the making of humanity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1990. Practical reason and norms, 2nd ed (with new postscript). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, M. 2008. Ritual and the sacred: A Neo-Durkheimian analysis of politics, religion and the self. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A. 1951/2004. On law and justice. Clark: The Lawbook Exchange (original Danish version: 1951)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. 2004. The limited domain of the law. Virginia Law Review 90: 1909–1956.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. 1934/2004. On the three types of juristic thought. Westport: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, A., et al. 2008. Ritual and its consequences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winn, P.A. 1992. Legal ritual. Law and Critique 2(2): 207–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Croce, M. (2012). The Ritual Dimension of Law: Normality, Normativity, and Critique. In: Self-sufficiency of Law. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 99. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4298-7_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics