Skip to main content

Does Biology Need a New Theory of Explanation? A Biological Perspective on Kant’s Critique of Teleological Judgment

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Origin(s) of Design in Nature

Part of the book series: Cellular Origin, Life in Extreme Habitats and Astrobiology ((COLE,volume 23))

Abstract

In 1790, Immanuel Kant completed and published the final installment of his three Critiques. With these, he addressed and changed our world perspective on some of the most fundamental problems with which human knowledge had been wrestling. The nature of these Critiques is, amazingly, from a twenty-first-century biologist perspective, still important and relevant in our rapidly evolving discipline to this day, a consequence of the depth and clarity of thought that appeared on the pages Kant presented to the reader. It also provides us with a wealth of bases to reassess problems that we had perhaps in our hubris thought solved in the relentless wave of scientific discovery, or at least had withered away from old age to inconsequential dust. But, as we so often find, dust may merely cover something from view, but in no way affect the structure of the object itself. And with this understanding, it is perhaps time to dust off Kant’s third Critique and use it to investigate the “sleeping giant” problem of teleology and design-like nature of organisms and assess how this work may inform our understandings of organisms and the process of life in the current day environment.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As a background, Kant, like earlier philosophers, distinguished between two types of propositions, synthetic and analytic. These can be further divided into two other types, a priori and empirical (a posteriori).

    A priori propositions: have fundamental validity, they are not based on perception, for example, “7  +  5  =  12” or “all bachelors are unmarried men.” They are available without appeal to experience.

    Empirical (a posteriori) propositions: depend upon sense perception, for example, “the cat is black” or “the earth moves around the sun.” Humans, Kant contends, can only judge by what they see and experience, that is, by what is empirical.

    Analytic propositions: the predicate is implicate in the subject, for example, “the black cat is black” or “bachelors are unmarried men.” For analytic propositions, the truth is discovered by analysis of the concept itself.

    Synthetic propositions: those propositions that cannot be arrived at by pure analysis, for example, “the cat is on the mat.” In these propositions, the predicate is not included in the subject; you need to go and investigate its truth.

    Synthetic a priori propositions: have an a priori base but are also synthetic (whereas other a priori propositions are analytic). For example, between any two points is one straight line. You cannot get insight into this truth by merely investigating your concept of straight lines or points. The nature of space also has to be considered, which has to be investigated empirically. Synthetic a priori propositions show us the limits of our view on reality when we investigate them.

  2. 2.

    Discursive understanding is knowledge yielded through the understanding through concepts, and thus is ultimately filtered through and limited in scope by the categories. It picks out features that things have in common with other things and applies concepts to them. It is interchangeable with “judgment” and “thought.”

10. References

  • Bohm D (1980) Wholeness and the implicate order. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Calendar R, Abedon ST (2006) The bacteriophages. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Collings PJ (2002) Liquid crystals: nature’s delicate state of matter. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Grene M, Depew D (2004) The philosophy of biology: an episodic history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1982) Philosophy and biology. In: Fløistad G (ed) Contemporary philosophy, a new survey. Philosophy of science, vol 2. Nijhoff, pp 280–316

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1965) The critique of pure reason (Smith NK, trans.). St Martin’s Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1987) The critique of judgment (Pluhar WS, trans.). Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1993) Critique of practical reason (Beck LW, trans.). MacMillan Publishing, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lima-de-Faria A (1988) Evolution without selection: form and function by autoevolution. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Lima-de-Faria A (1995) Biological periodicity: its molecular mechanism and evolutionary implications. JAI Press Inc., Greenwich

    Google Scholar 

  • McFarland JD (1970) Kant’s concept of teleology. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Petoukhov SV (2002) Solitons of living matter and biomechanics of movements. Acta Bioeng Biomech 4(Suppl 1):578

    Google Scholar 

  • Prusinkiewicz P, Lindenmayer A (1996) The algorithmic beauty of plants (The virtual laboratory). Springer, Heidelberg

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1942) On growth and form. Cambridge University Press, London

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Webster G, Goodwin BC (1982) The origin of species: a structuralist approach. J Social Biol Struct 5:15–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weibel ER (1991) Fractal geometry: a design principle for living organisms. Am J Physiol 261(6 Pt 1):L361–L369

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicks R (1994) Hegel’s theory of aesthetic judgment. Peter Lang Publishing, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

9. Acknowledgments

Thanks to Bob Wicks and Wayne Waxman and Dave Lambert for discussions, wisdom, and clarifications.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Chetland .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Chetland, C. (2012). Does Biology Need a New Theory of Explanation? A Biological Perspective on Kant’s Critique of Teleological Judgment. In: Swan, L., Gordon, R., Seckbach, J. (eds) Origin(s) of Design in Nature. Cellular Origin, Life in Extreme Habitats and Astrobiology, vol 23. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4156-0_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics