Skip to main content

“Rambam or Maimonides”

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Reading Maimonides' Philosophy in 19th Century Germany

Part of the book series: Amsterdam Studies in Jewish Philosophy ((ASJT,volume 15))

  • 547 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter discusses the reaction of German Jewish Orthodoxy to the liberal Maimonides renaissance in the nineteenth and early twentieth century – analysing the reading of Maimonidean philosophy by Orthodox thinkers such as Samson Raphael Hirsch, Josef Gugenheimer, Simon Eppenstein, Joseph Wohlgemuth and David Z. Hoffmann. It will be argued that although those reactions evolve from Samson Raphael Hirsch’s outright rejection of the Guide in 1836, to a meaningful orthodox cooperation in cross-stream research projects concerning Maimonides’ work at the beginning of the twentieth century, there generally remains a clear difference between the liberal and orthodox interpreters of the Guide: Orthodox readings almost always retreat to supernatural Sinaitic revelation as the source of Judaism’s essence, and would rather accuse the Guide of dissembling argumentation in order to address Jews perplexed by philosophy than attribute any kind of non-traditionalist position to the author of the Mishneh Torah.

It will be demonstrated that even the most objective and apparently non-apologetic attempts to reclaim Maimonides for Orthodox Judaism must ultimately and inevitably end in an outspoken rejection of rationalism and a return to ‘arbitrary’ revelation. It is this misunderstanding between the Reformers and neo-Orthodoxy that causes the continuous debates between the two camps discussed in this chapter: that for the traditionalist side it is self-evident, and neither open for argument nor subject to formal proof, that the intuitive discovery of ‘God’s will’, and the therefore assumed fact that the commandments are the product of this will, is the bedrock foundation for the obligation to keep them faithfully.

Interestingly, the more philosophical implications of this antagonism are reflected, as will be shown in an appendix to the chapter, almost par for par in the well-known debate between Leo Strauss and Julius Guttmann about the relevance of religious philosophy in the modern world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Der Orient 1840, No. 15, p. 235.

  2. 2.

     Joseph Klein in Monatsschrift für Geschichte und Wissenschaft des Judentums 1863, No. 6, p. 203.

  3. 3.

     For Bamberger and the entire subject, see also Carsten Wilke Den Talmud und den Kant, Hildesheim 2003, p. 230. Nevertheless, there are certain differences between those three rabbis: While Rosenfeld introduced at least some aesthetic reforms, Bamberger and Benet were strictly opposed to change. Benet, though, in 1816 gave his approbation for a new edition of Mendelssohn’s German Bible translation. For even earlier Orthodox readers of the Guide, see Steven Harvey “The Introductions of Early Enlightenment Thinkers as Harbingers of the Renewed Interest in the Medieval Jewish Philosophers”, in: Sepharad in Ashkenaz: Medieval Knowledge and Eighteenth-Century Enlightened Jewish Discourse (ed. by Resianne Fontaine, Andrea Schatz and Irene Zwiep), Amsterdam 2007, p. 85ff.

  4. 4.

     In fact, “Orthodoxy” begins only with the time of the enlightenment. But in order to emphasize the enormous difference between pre-Enlightenment Judaism and modern, Western Orthodoxy the term neo-Orthodox makes sense. See here: Adam Ferziger who in his Exclusion and Hierarchy (Philadelphia 2005) connects the origin of Orthodoxy to to non-observance becoming a legitimate behavior for a majority of Jews.

  5. 5.

     Samson Raphael Hirsch Neunzehn Briefe über Judentum, Altona 1836, p. 98. English: Samson Raphael Hirsch The Nineteen Letters, newly translated by Karin Paritzky, revised and with a comprehensive commentary by Joseph Elias, Jerusalem 1995, p. 266. The earlier English translation by Bernard Drachmann omits the German part “und musste daher geistlos sinken – ja verachtet werden.” See Nineteen Letters on Judaism, New York 1960, p. 120.

  6. 6.

     There is no room here to discuss Hirsch’s views on symbols in Judaism; see his “Grundlinien einer jüdischen Symbolik”, in: Gesammelte Schriften III, p. 213–268, and for discussion David Ellenson After Emancipation, Cinncinati 2004, p. 246ff. and Meir Seidler “Solving the Most Urgent Problems of Jewish Consciousness – Rabbi Samson Raphael Hirsch’s Symbolism and its Historical Background” (Hebrew) in: Binyamin Ish Shalom (ed.), BeDarke Shalom – Iyunim beHagut Yehudit, Jerusalem 2007, p. 323–351.

  7. 7.

    Neunzehn Briefe p. 99f. For Hirsch’s anti-Maimonideanism in the Nineteen Letters, see also Michah Gottlieb “Counter-Enlightenment in a Jewish Key: Anti-Maimonideanism in Nineteenth-Century Orthodoxy”, in: The Cultures of Maimonideanism (ed. James T. Robinson), Leiden 2009, p. 270–87 and Michael A. Meyer “Maimonides and Some Moderns”, in CCAR Journal, 1997, p. 4–15.

  8. 8.

     Max Wiener Jüdische Religion im Zeitalter der Emanzipation, Berlin 1933, p. 74–79. David Sorkin (“Between Messianism and Survival”, in: Journal of Modern Jewish Studies 3,1 (2004), p. 76) would go as far as calling Hirsch’s neo-Orthodoxy “a distinct mutation” of traditional Judaism. See here also Moshe Samet “The Beginnings of Orthodoxy”, in: Modern Judaism 8,3 (1988) p. 249–269.

  9. 9.

     For background see Robert Liberles Religious Conflict in Social Context: The Resurgence of Orthodox Judaism in Frankfurt-am-Main, 1838–1877, Westport, Conn. 1985 and Matthias Morgenstern From Frankfurt to Jerusalem, Boston 2002, p. 126ff..

  10. 10.

     Samson Raphael Hirsch “Die Religion im Bund mit dem Fortschritt”, in: Gesammelte Schriften III, Frankfurt 1906, p. 504–508.

  11. 11.

     Ibid., p. 509. English translation in Samson Raphael Hirsch Judaism Eternal, London 1976, vol. II, p. 239–44.

  12. 12.

     TB Berachot 61b. The letter to Muhr is published in Proben aus dem literarischen Nachlasse des Herrn Israel Deutsch (ed. A. and D. Deutsch), Gleiwitz 1855, p. 98f.. For further discussion see Ismar Schorsch “The Emergence of the Modern Rabbinate”, in: Revolution and Evolution (ed. W.E. Mosse et al.), Tübingen 1981, p. 220–27.

  13. 13.

     Proben, p. 99. Little Foxes probably refers to Song of Songs 2:15. The term is often used in medieval Jewish literature to designate heretics and others who undermine Judaism, even by Maimonides himself.

  14. 14.

     For German neo-Orthodox explanations of the theological relevance of the sacrifice references in the prayer book, see David H. Ellenson “Sacrifice and Atonement in the Literature of German-Jewish Orthodoxy”, in his collection Between Tradition and Culture, Atlanta 1994, p. 27–40, and the account of the discussion about the liberal Baden Sidur below.

  15. 15.

     See Chap. 2 for discussion.

  16. 16.

     J. Bukofzer Maimonides im Streit mit seinem neuesten Biographen Peter Beer, Berlin 1844, preface p. xiv. I was unable to find biographical information about the author. Bukofzer knows not only Beer’s biography of Maimonides, he also seems to be a regular reader of Geiger’s Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift für Jüdische Theologie, from which he quotes articles by Creizenach and the Derenbourg review of the same biography.

  17. 17.

     Bukofzer, preface p. xiv. See Lebensgeschichte des Peter Beer, ed. by Moritz Herrmann, Prag 1839 and Louise Hecht Ein jüdischer Aufklärer in Böhmen: Der Pädagoge und Reformer Peter Beer, Böhlau 2008.

  18. 18.

     Bukofzer Maimonides im Streit, p. 36 note, see also p. 38.

  19. 19.

     Bukofzer Maimonides im Streit, p. 39. Bukofzer devotes long passages of his brochure to the refutation of the claim that Maimonides in his youth converted to Islam. He would even go so far as to claim that the excerpts of Maimonides’ Igeret haShmad that Eliakim Carmoly had published in 1839 were pure inventions. (p. 79f, see Chap. 3 of this study for details. It was only in 1850 that Geiger published for the first time a Hebrew translation of the complete text of Maimonides’ epistle.) Julius Fürst, in a contemporary review of Bukofzer’s book, wrote that, given the author’s strong rejection of the “fairy tale” about Maimonides’ conversion to Islam, the reviewer might condone some of the “sins regarding form and content” of the book. (Literaturblatt des Orient 1845, No. 26, p. 406.)

  20. 20.

     Bukofzer Maimonides im Streit, p. 62. Maimonides makes it clear at the end of Guide III:32 that for him the sacrifices belong to the lowest group of commandments.

  21. 21.

     Bukofzer Maimonides im Streit, p. 77.

  22. 22.

     Josef Gugenheimer (1833–1896) officiated first as rabbi of Těšín (Silesia), beginning in 1859 in Stuhlweissenburg (Hungary), where he resigned after two years when his efforts to return the community to traditional Judaism failed, and then officiated for 30 years in Colin (Bohemia). See his Die Religionsphilosophie des Abraham ben David, Augsburg 1850. The history of Reform in Stuhlweissenburg is interesting in itself: the Orthodox president of the community, Gottlieb Fischer, was instrumental in Hirsch’s campaign against both the Breslau seminary and Frankel, writing an aggressive review of Frankel’s book on the Mishnah. In this review, Fischer, referring to Maimonides’ Thirteen Principles, attempts to delegitimize Frankel’s authority as rabbi and teacher. (See Jeschurun 1860, p. 210) Later, Hirsch himself intervened in Stuhlweissenburg in order to prevent a rapprochement of the factions in the community.

  23. 23.

    Jeschurun 1856, No. 7, p. 387. For Löw and his book, see Chap. 4 of this thesis.

  24. 24.

     Ibid., p. 389.

  25. 25.

     Ibid., p. 390.

  26. 26.

     Leopold Löw “Zur Maimonidesfrage”, Ben Chananja 1858, p. 145–157.

  27. 27.

     Hoffmann, who first taught in Frankfurt, had broken with Hirsch after the latter condemned Hoffmann’s doctoral thesis from 1871, a biography of the Talmudic sage Mar Samuel. Subsequently, Hoffmann came to Berlin to teach under Hildesheimer. (See for this episode Mordechai Breuer Jüdische Orthodoxie im Deutschen Reich, Frankfurt 1986, p. 171f.)

  28. 28.

     Cf. for this program Joseph Wohlgemuth’s essay on the occasion of the fiftieth anniversary of the seminary in Jeschurun 10, 1923, p. 317ff.

  29. 29.

     Ludwig Stein Die Willensfreiheit und ihr Verhältnis zur göttlichen Präscienz und Providenz bei den jüdischen Philosophen des Mittelalters, Berlin 1882, p. 29. Stein reads Maimonides throughout as a supporter of the rabbinic system of reward and punishment, despite some contrary passages towards the end of the Guide. For Stein’s biography, see Chap. 4.

  30. 30.

     Ignatz Münz Die Religionsphilosophie des Maimonides und ihr Einfluss, Berlin 1887 (Dissertation Leipzig) p. 13.

  31. 31.

     Ibid. p. 16f.

  32. 32.

     Ignaz Münz Moses ben Maimon, sein Leben und seine Werke, Frankfurt 1912, p. 111. Münz, who belongs to a family of rabbis, published the first four chapters of the book already in 1902, but only the complete work from 1912 contains his discussion of the Guide.

  33. 33.

     Ibid. This doctrine, though, stands in contrast to the opposition that the Mishneh Torah also met when it first appeared – but this is not the subject of the present study.

  34. 34.

     Ibid., p. 200.

  35. 35.

     Ibid., p. 211.

  36. 36.

     Ibid., p. 212.

  37. 37.

     Ibid., p. 246f.

  38. 38.

     David Hoffmann Das Buch Leviticus, 2 vols, Berlin 1905, vol 1, p. 79.

  39. 39.

     Hoffmann claims that Abarbanel’s reading of the midrash in question (LevR 22:8) is wrong. But even if right, it would prove too much: nowhere does Maimonides say that the sacrifices are uncalled for, as the midrash in Abarbanel’s reading seems to suggest (Hoffmann, Leviticus, p. 82). See the remark of Isaac Heinemann who believes that it is rather our reading of Abarbanel that is wrong in this case (The Reasons for the Commandments in Jewish Thought, transl. L. Levin, Brighton 2008, p. 153, note). Against Hoffmann’s view stands a long list of scholars writing before and after him: David Cassel (Commentary on Kuzari, p. 129), Shaul Rabinowiz, the Hebrew translator of Graetz’ History (vol. IV, p. 394), Mordechai Margulies in his edition of the midrash (ad locum, New York 1993), and Ephraim Urbach (Sages, p. 368), all of whom believe as did Abarbanel that the midrash might have been a source for Maimonides’ theory. Menachem Kellner (Maimonides’ Confrontation with Mysticism, p. 153), following Jonathan Klawan, claims that Maimonides himself was unaware of the support he could have found in this midrash – for while referring to LevR many times in the Guide, the passage in question is not quoted. As discussed in Chap. 7, as early as 1841 Gotthold Salomon and Samuel Holdheim refer to the midrash and to Abarbanel in their respective defenses of the Hamburg Reform prayer book against Isaac Bernays. (Gotthold Salomon Das neue Gebetbuch und seine Verketzerung, Hamburg 1841, p. 19 and Samuel Holdheim Verketzerung und Gewissensfreiheit, Hamburg 1842, p. 62.)

  40. 40.

     Hoffmann, Leviticus, p. 86.

  41. 41.

     Hoffmann, Leviticus, p. 86f. (my emphasis) Interestingly, Hoffmann himself ruled sometimes according to ‘changed times and circumstances’; see for example a responsum on conversion to Judaism where he seems to argue that because of the new option of civil marriage, the Talmudic dictum (Yebamoth 24b) that no conversion must be performed for the purpose of marriage is no longer valid, for if the couple explicitly decided against civil marriage for the religious option, this amounts to a motive le shem shamaim as the Talmud demands. See Hoffmann’s collection of responsa Melamed Leho’il, New York 1954, No. 2:85, p. 89.

  42. 42.

     At the beginning of the twentieth century, Hoffman was the final authority on halacha for traditional German Jewry. For Hoffmann as a halachic decisor, see David Ellenson Tradition in Transition, Lanham 1989, p. 47–57 and passim. Already in 1885, Hoffmann had published a brochure in defense of the Orthodox position towards non-Jews; see David Hoffmann Der Shulchan Aruch und die Rabbinen über das Verhältnis der Juden zu den Andersgläubigen, Berlin 1885. Hoffmann’s attempt to refute Wellhausen is in David Hoffmann Die wichtigsten Instancen gegen die Graf-Wellhausensche Hypothese, Berlin 1902.

  43. 43.

     Heinrich Graetz Geschichte der Juden, vol. 6 (2nd edition), p. 322. For Graetz’ ambiguous position towards Reform, see Chap. 3.

  44. 44.

     David Hoffmann Zur Aufklärung über die badische Gebetbuchreform: Ein Sendschreiben an den “Verein zur Wahrung des gesetzestreuen Judentums in Baden”, Rödelheim 1908, p. 23.

  45. 45.

     Moritz Steckelmacher Widerlegung des Sendschreibens des Dr. D. Hoffmann, Mannheim 1908, p. 25. Steckelmacher seems to refer to Maimonides’ Book of Commandments (Positive Commandment 187) where Maimonides writes “This mitzvah [destroying the Seven Canaanite Nations] was fully completed by King David…” – see also Laws of Kings and Wars 6:4 where Maimonides in any case conditions their destruction to the refusal to accept a peaceful settlement.

  46. 46.

     Steckelmacher Widerlegung, p. 33. Maimonides himself uses this verse from Deuteronomy in the same context; see Guide III:31. For a detailed discussion of Steckelmacher’s response, see Chap. 4.

  47. 47.

     Eppenstein (1864–1920) was born in Korotschin. From 1884 to 1889 he studied first in Breslau and later at the Hildesheimer seminary, and officiated afterwards for more than 20 years in the town of Briesen (West Prussia). From 1911 he taught Jewish history and Bible exegesis at the seminary as the successor to Abraham Berliner. He was an uncle of the liberal Rabbi Max Dienemann.

  48. 48.

     Simon Eppenstein “Moses ben Maimon, ein Lebens- und Charakterbild”, in: Moses ben Maimon, sein Leben, seine Werke und sein Einfluss (ed. Jacob Guttmann et al.), vol II, Leipzig 1914, p. 80f.

  49. 49.

     Ibid., p. 82. Ibn Gabirol’s authorship of Fons Vitæ was in fact rediscovered only in 1846 by Salomon Munk.

  50. 50.

     Ibid., p. 84.

  51. 51.

     Achad Ha’am , in:, vol XV, S. 307ff. For discussion see Eliezer Schweid Jewish Thought in the 20 th Century, Atlanta 1992, p. 298–300.

  52. 52.

     Joseph Wohlgemuth (1867–1942) grew up in Hamburg and studied at the Hildesheimer seminar in Berlin, as well as at the Berlin University. In 1895 he was appointed lecturer in religious philosophy, homiletics, and practical halachah at the seminary, where he exercised considerable influence on several generations of students for the Orthodox rabbinate. Together with Isaak Bleichrode, Wohlgemuth published in 1899 a popular German Bible translation. In 1914 he resuscitated Hirsch’s journal Jeschurun and edited it until 1930 as the ultimate mouthpiece of German neo-Orthodoxy.

  53. 53.

     Joseph Wohlgemuth “Achad Haam und das gesetzestreue Judentum”, in: Jeschurun 11 (1916), p. 605.

  54. 54.

     Wohlgemuth, p. 605. For discussion of the long tradition of a liberal position on Guide II:25,see Chap. 3.

  55. 55.

     Wohlgemuth, p. 606. More easily, however, he is able to refute Achad Ha’am’s nationalist approach to Maimonides. This is simply an “ahistorical extrapolation from the modern Zionist’s mind to the thinking of the greatest halachic authority after the Talmud.” Wohlgemuth charges Achad Ha’am with seeing Mosaic Law merely “as an empty national patrimony that he romantically loves.” (607)

  56. 56.

     See Cohen’s Religion der Vernunft aus den Quellen des Judentums, Frankfurt 1929, p. 381f. and Chap. 7 for discussion.

  57. 57.

     Leo Strauss would later propose the theory that, psychologically, it is always the more radical view of a thinker that is dearest to his heart, and that by this standard it is easy to identify Maimonides’ esoteric opinions. (Leo Strauss “The Literary Character of the Guide for the Perplexed”, in: Persecution and the Art of Writing, Chicago 1988)

  58. 58.

     A critical edition of Nahmanides’ epistle was published by Joseph Perles (one of the first Breslau graduates) in the Monatsschrift as early as 1860 (No. 5, p. 184–195, the passage in question is on p. 186f.).

  59. 59.

    Laws of Kings and Wars 11:1.

  60. 60.

     A good example is Joseph Elias’ commentary on Hirsch’s eighteenth letter, published in 1995 in the new English edition of the Nineteen Letters. Elias struggles hard to come to terms both with Hirsch’s bold criticism of the Rambam but also with Maimonides’ theories from the Guide that gave rise to Hirsch’s opinion in the first place. After quoting many rabbinical sources to the effect that Maimonides was forced to write philosophy only in order to address the views of confused people, he agrees with Hirsch that Maimonides himself would have consigned the Guide to the flames had he been witness to the misuse of the treatise. (The Nineteen Letters, Jerusalem 1995, p. 287–291.)

  61. 61.

     Israel Friedländer “Moses Maimonides”, in Jeschurun 1916, No. 7, p. 367f. (only the last installment deals with the Guide).

  62. 62.

     Friedländer p. 368.

  63. 63.

     All quotes Friedländer p. 372.

  64. 64.

     As opposed to that, Spinoza (Tractatus, ch. 9) maintains that Ibn Ezra in his commentary on Deuteronomy in fact denied the Mosaic authorship of the Torah. See Warren Z. Harvey “Spinoza on Ibn Ezra’s Secret of the Twelve”, in: Spinoza’s “Theological-Political Treatise”; a Critical Guide, ed. Y.Y. Melamed and M.A. Rosenthal, Cambridge 2010, p. 41–55.

  65. 65.

     Friedländer p. 373.

  66. 66.

     Friedländer p. 374f.

  67. 67.

     Friedländer p. 375f.

  68. 68.

     Friedländer p. 376.

  69. 69.

     Friedländer, p. 377.

  70. 70.

     Arnold (Abraham) Klein (1875–1961) was the rabbi of Nuremberg’s Orthodox Adas Jisrael community from 1909 until 1939, when Klein emigrated to Palestine.

  71. 71.

     Arnold Klein “Rambam oder Maimonides”, in: Festschrift J. Rosenheim, Frankfurt 1931, p. 218f.

  72. 72.

     See Hirsch’s commentary on Exodus 21, 1–2.

  73. 73.

     Klein, p. 222.

  74. 74.

     Klein, p. 222f.

  75. 75.

     Klein, p. 224f. Emphasis in the original.

  76. 76.

     The debate has found widespread scholarly interest and will be discussed here only in the context of the thrust of the present chapter, i.e. within the context of the argument about the Guide between liberal and Orthodox German Jewish scholars. I draw especially on Eliezer Schweid “Religion and Philosophy: The Scholarly Debate between Julius Guttmann and Leo Strauss”, in: Maimonidean Studies 1 (1990), p. 163–195, because Schweid’s conclusions come closest to my own reading of the debate. But see also: Kenneth Hart Green Jew and Philosopher: The Return to Maimonides in the Jewish Thought of Leo Strauss, New York 1993, p. 45f and 104ff.; Jonathan Cohen Philosophers and Scholars: Wolfson, Guttmann and Strauss on the History of Jewish Philosophy. Lanham, MD 2007, p. 260ff (although Cohen for some reason does not discuss Guttmann’s reply); Thomas Meyer Zwischen Philosophie und Gesetz, Leiden 2009, p. 74–106 and Mari Rethelyi “Guttmann’s Critique of Strauss’s Modernist Approach to Medieval Philosophy”, in: Journal of Textual Reasoning 3, 1 (2004).

  77. 77.

     Julius Guttmann “Philosophie der Religion oder Philosophie des Gesetzes”, in: Proceedings of the IsraelAcademy of Science 5,6 (1976), p. 170. Guttmann’s essay seems to be based also on knowledge of Strauss’ later article about the “Literary Character of the Guide”, first published in Essays on Maimonides, New York, 1941. Strauss’ original critique is in his Philosophie und Gesetz, Berlin 1935, (translated by Eve Adler as Philosophy and Law, Albany 1995). For a more general history of Maimonides reception, see Warren Zev Harvey “The Return of Maimonideanism”, in: Jewish Social Studies 42 (1980), p. 249–68.

  78. 78.

     ‘Internalize’ is Strauss’s term, see Philosophy and Law, p. 24ff.

  79. 79.

     Explicitly attacking nineteenth-century thought, Strauss’ follower, Shlomo Pines, has shown how, by this logic of esotericism, Spinoza, one of Maimonides’ harshest critics, turns into what must have been Maimonides’ favorite reader. This is because Spinoza mercilessly “tracked down the inconsistencies and contradictions of the Guide.” (See Shlomo Pines “Spinoza’s Tractatus, Maimonides and Kant”, in: Studies in the History of Jewish Thought, ed. Moshe Idel and Zev Harvey, Jerusalem 1997, p. 661.) Compare here Manuel Joel’s book-length defense of Maimonides against Spinoza: Spinoza’s Theologisch-Politischer Traktat auf seine Quellen geprüft, Breslau 1870.

  80. 80.

     Schweid, p. 191. For Geiger and Graetz, cf. chapters 3 and 7. See for this issue also Herbert A. Davidson “The Study of Philosophy as a Religious Obligation”, in: Religion in a Religious Age (ed. S. D. Goitein), Cambridge 1974, p. 53–64.

  81. 81.

     See Schweid, p. 192.

  82. 82.

     Guttmann, p. 160. Regardless of the content, the purpose of revelation for Maimonides is, according to Guttmann, completely different from what Strau  ss assumed: it is not political but must be seen essentially in the intellectual perfection of the individual man. (163)

  83. 83.

     In Guttmann’s summary of Strauss’ position, p. 169.

  84. 84.

     Strauss Philosophy and Law, p. 37f.

  85. 85.

     Guttmann, p. 170f.

  86. 86.

     Guttmann p. 171. That Strauss also represents here a certain intellectual school becomes clear from the example of Harry A. Wolfson, the great historian of religious philosophy. Like Strauss raised in traditional Orthodox surroundings but later turned secular, Wolfson adopted similar views concerning the concept of God. In a ‘Sermonette’ from 1955, he denounced all non-traditional, non-scriptural, non-personal, that is, all philosophical concepts of God as “substitute gods”, accusing philosophers of being “engaged in the gentle art of devising deities.” But one has to either believe in the God that people believe in – or else confess to being an atheist, according to Wolfson. (See Harry. A. Wolfson Religious Philosophy, Cambridge 1961, p. 270f.) The liberal school around Cohen, to which Guttmann still belongs in a fashion, believed in the progressive development of the concept of God from polytheist mysticism to monotheist idealism, with Maimonides’ attack on anthropomorphism and his theory of the sacrifices clearly supporting the move away from mysticism.

  87. 87.

     For this conclusion see also Schweid’s summary on p. 193.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Appendix: The Debate Between Julius Guttmann and Leo Strauss

Appendix: The Debate Between Julius Guttmann and Leo Strauss

The well-known controversy between Julius Guttmann and Leo Strauss about the relevance of religious philosophy in the modern world reflects almost par for par the antagonism between a rational theology as a compromise between religious considerations and philosophical necessities on the one hand, and the non-rational insistence on the supernatural character of revelation next to rational philosophy on the other.Footnote 76 Supporting the latter view, Leo Strauss had devoted a full chapter of his “Philosophy and Law” (1935) to a thorough and harsh criticism of Guttmann’s classic “Die Philosophie des Judentums” from 1933, which proposed the former position. Guttmann, in turn, formulated a lengthy response to Strauss’s attack only after 1940, when he was already teaching in Jerusalem, but never published it. This response, which was finally made public after being obtained from Guttmann’s Nachlaß in 1976, was not less aggressive than Strauss’s essay, at least regarding its content: Strauss’s main assessment, that the only possible alternatives in religious philosophy are Orthodoxy or atheism, is “lacking in every justification” – so declares Guttmann in what can be read as a powerful defense of Reform theology and its mediation between religion and philosophy – a defense based on the Maimonidean example.Footnote 77

Leo Strauss accused Guttmann, the neo-Kantian and student of Hermann Cohen, not only of supporting the failure, as it seemed to Strauss, of harmonizing philosophy and religion within a modern religious philosophy of Judaism, Strauss extended his criticism also to the reading of medieval Jewish philosophy by the liberal school of Jewish scholars – in what seems to be a circular argument. Since for Strauss, religious orthodoxy cannot be disproved rationally, to “internalize” irrational assumptions of belief (revelation or creation), as the liberal theologians undertook, will only abrogate those beliefs and destroy the authenticity of religion.Footnote 78 But this strict anti-Reform claim caused a serious dilemma for Strauss: Maimonides seems to say in the Guide over and again that precisely this rational internalization of dogma is at the core of his intention in the treatise. Ironically, Maimonides, and especially his teachings in the Guide, is the shield bearer for both sides of the debate. Strauss demands a ‘return to Maimonides’ because he believes that the Guide contains the key to the most effective solution of the problem of the relation between philosophy and religion, while Guttmann saw Maimonides’ thought rather as a certain stage in the continuous progress towards, but (in a Kantian way) never-to-be-completed solution of this same problem. While for Guttmann, Maimonides’ main concern is an exegetical one – the contradiction between the peshat and a metaphorically hidden, true meaning of the Bible – for Strauss it is entirely a legal one. Strauss is asking two questions that are actually not far from Hermann Cohen’s approach to the authority of the Torah, discussed above: Is there a commandment to speculate about religious truths – and: Is there rational authority for revelation? But in answering those questions completely differently from Cohen, Strauss reveals what he identified as the ultimate key for finding the correct relationship between belief and thinking, between revelation and speculation, which is to say, between religion and philosophy. Medieval Jewish philosophy, including that of Maimonides, Strauss claims, saw the validity of revelation first and foremost as a political issue. There is no commandment to philosophize about religion; revelation, for Strauss, is entirely a ‘postulate of political reason’. The ‘objective truth’ of revelation must be accepted in its irrationality not because of speculative results, but because of political and social necessities, where the absolute authority of the law is the core issue. The difference between the adept philosopher (or the prophet) and the uneducated masses, whom Maimonides refers to frequently, is not a bridgeable, empirical disparity, which will eventually be closed in Messianic times, as the Cohen school has read Maimonides – for Strauss it is insurmountable and must therefore be hidden under the claim of the invulnerable superiority of the law over philosophical conclusions. Such a position must necessarily lead to a theory of extreme esotericism concerning Maimonides on the part of Strauss. Given the incompatibility of revelation and philosophy, only esoterically can a rational approach to religion be found, an approach that will more or less end up as speculative atheism; or, in Maimonides’ case, at best in the acknowledgment of Aristotle’s unmovable first cause of the world.Footnote 79

Guttmann’s answer to this theory is clear: Maimonides had not only intended the harmonization of religion and philosophy, he in fact achieved such a synthesis with most of the teachings of the Guide. In the same way as Geiger and Graetz before him, Guttmann holds that in Judaism, philosophical thought about religion in the light of the Guide became “an inseparable part of the religious tradition itself.”Footnote 80 Philosophical speculation was seen in Judaism, at the latest after Maimonides’ arguments, as commanded by the Law itself, and the intellectual interpretation of religious contents was practiced by many legal authorities – in the same way that the Reform Movement had always claimed was the case in justification of its own halachic efforts. While Strauss had to deny Maimonides’ declared intention of harmonization between Bible and reason, Guttmann’s approach only needs to find an explanation for the apparent internal contradictions that the Guide contains concerning some matters of Jewish tradition. Here Guttmann also retreats to the position of the liberal interpretation, formulated by many thinkers from the Breslau School: those contradictions are not intentional but “innocent failures” to provide a consistent solution, given the limited philosophical tools that were available to Maimonides.Footnote 81

For Guttmann, Maimonides never acknowledged the primacy of revelation over reason, and always attempted what Guttmann calls a ‘coordination’ of the two concepts in his philosophy. The difference between this approach and modern philosophy is that medieval thinking “retained so much elemental belief in revelation” that, even if the autonomy of reason is supposed to authenticate revelation, the conclusions of this process actually dictate the way reason is used from the start.Footnote 82 For Strauss, however, the difference from modern philosophy is categorical: Enlightenment had introduced the belief that reason is entirely self-sufficient, thereby building up the insurmountable antagonism between reason and revelation. Here, every attempted synthesis (as by Mendelssohn) is only “a veiled capitulation” by true religion, every ‘internalization’ of religious principles (as by the Reformers) only “a concealed denial of the apparently restored foundations of faith.”Footnote 83 Judaism, for Strauss, can only have the character of pure and non-intellectualized belief in tradition, the alternative of which is atheism.Footnote 84 To deny this consequence, and to attempt to find a way of reconciliation of orthodox dogma and rational thought, amounts to philosophical dishonesty.

This now is the point where Guttmann voiced his strongest criticism of Strauss’s views. Although by the 1940s he had departed from many convictions of his teacher Cohen, Guttmann’s answer cannot be read but as a broad defense of what has been the firm position of liberal German Jewish theology throughout the nineteenth century – Guttmann’s intellectual home – and what found in Cohen its most eloquent representative. “If Orthodoxy is rooted only in faith”, Guttmann writes, “then it is a dogmatic claim to power that no other form of faith is possible next to it. It is a petitio principii to view every faith that is not bound by dogma as a mere ‘mediation’ [Vermittlung] between Orthodoxy and unbelief, and to stigmatize it, because of its mediating character, as dishonest.”Footnote 85 The intellectual comfort that a philosophical idea of God offered to religious thinkers from many different centuries is strictly rejected by Strauss; he denies the existence of God exactly because of the comfort that this idea offers, according to Guttmann.Footnote 86 Strauss however upholds revelation, according to Guttmann, only because he cannot believe in the self-sufficiency of reason. Moreover, claims Guttmann, Strauss’s pessimistic outlook on the world in general and on the intellectual abilities of humankind in particular dictates that faith can only arise from man’s feeling of impotence. But if this is true, the content of revelation becomes indeed irrelevant, as long as the legal character of revelation meets man’s need for authority.

This legal formalism cannot be the last word on modern religious philosophy, according to Guttmann. Both Maimonides and the liberal theological tradition of the nineteenth century had always emphasized not only the eternal value of the actual content of Biblical revelation, but to an even greater degree the ethical meaning of the purpose of divine legislation. Thus, for Guttmann, philosophical thinking, even in modernity, must surely include religion – seen here as an intellectual activity – since philosophy is supposed to cover all aspects of human reason. Gaining knowledge of God, in Maimonides’ sense, is a religious obligation for Guttmann, and inasmuch as philosophy must cover religious thought, religious thought must be applied to the world using the methods of philosophical speculation.Footnote 87

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kohler, G.Y. (2012). “Rambam or Maimonides”. In: Reading Maimonides' Philosophy in 19th Century Germany. Amsterdam Studies in Jewish Philosophy, vol 15. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4035-8_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics