Skip to main content

“It All Depends”: The Universal and the Contingent in Human Rights

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophical Dimensions of Human Rights

Abstract

In considering various conventional objections against the universalist conceptions of human rights, it is important to distinguish between those objections which can be articulated as the charge of intolerance from those which are better articulated as the charge of paternalism. While the former are implausible, the latter may be sometimes correct but it is arguable that the paternalism a play is of an unobjectionable variety. But even if we dispel (as I will try to) the charges of an objectionable form of intolerance or paternalism leveled at a universalist project of human rights, we do not thereby satisfy ourselves about the feasibility of such an aspiration. There are clear limits to the feasibility of the universalist project, and the structure of human-rights discourse is such that certain factual factors which are built into this discourse are crucially context-dependent. The main types of such factors are described in this chapter as “justificatory”, “empirical” and “institutional”, and case studies are provided to exemplify each category.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Gardbaum (1996).

  2. 2.

    Rawls (1999, 59, see also 84). It should be remembered that respect for human rights is one of the requirements with which non-liberal but “decent” societies (which, in Rawls’s view, are “members in good standing” of an international Society of Peoples) must comply with.

  3. 3.

    Williams (1982, 172); see also Williams (1985, 159).

  4. 4.

    See Sadurski (1996, 378).

  5. 5.

    See, similarly, Barry (2001, 138).

  6. 6.

    See, e.g., Cassese (1999).

  7. 7.

    Harman (1996, 190); see also, similarly, in Harman and Thomson (1996, 59–61).

  8. 8.

    For a critique, see Sadurski (1990, 70–86).

  9. 9.

    See Thompson (2001, 154–65). See also, similarly, Dworkin (2002).

  10. 10.

    Dr Anwar Ibrahim, quoted in, The Economist (1998, 25).

  11. 11.

    Dr Anwar Ibrahim, The Economist (1998, 25).

  12. 12.

    Rawls (1993, 50, emphases added). Note that this quotation comes from an earlier article by Rawls upon which his book was to be subsequently based. I have not located an equivalent statement in the book but neither have I found any clear, or even implicit, repudiation of the view expressed in the statement. In fact, there are several implicit reiterations of this point; for instance, in the context of his rejection of an idea of “global original positions” in which all persons (as opposed to peoples or their governments) participated, Rawls adds: “The Law of Peoples proceeds from the international political world as we see it….” (Rawls 1993, 83, emphasis added).

  13. 13.

    Rawls admits that societies which “honor human rights” but whose members “are denied a meaningful role in making political decisions” are not well-ordered (Rawls 1993, 4).

  14. 14.

    See, e.g., Sartorius (1983, ix); Feinberg ( 1986, 3–8).

  15. 15.

    More on this distinction, in the context of freedom of speech, see Sadurski (1999, 173–78).

  16. 16.

    For discussions of such a “mild,” ignorance-removing paternalism, see, inter alia, Feinberg (1986, 269–315); Dworkin (1983, 28–33).

  17. 17.

    Elster (1983, esp. Chap. III). See also Sunstein (1986, 1146–50).

  18. 18.

    The proportionality proviso is important because we may imagine an objectionable paternalism which is applied to people whose preferences have been defectively formed but where paternalism does not track those specific defects but rather follows from a general attitude of disregard for avowed preferences of people.

  19. 19.

    For some typical expression of “color blindness” in the United States jurisprudence, see DeFunis v. Odegaard, 416 U.S. 312, 331–4 (1974) (Douglas, J., dissenting); Fullilove v. Klutznick, 448 U.S. 448, 523 (1980) (Stewart, J., dissenting); in the US legal scholarship: Bickel (1975, 132–3); Posner (1974).

  20. 20.

    As opposed to the speech which hurts people because of their unusual, eccentric sensitivities.

  21. 21.

    For two good discussions of different legal approaches to Holocaust denial, see Schmidt and Vojtovic (2000, 133–58); Cooper and Williams (1999, 593–613).

  22. 22.

    Universality, just as “fundamentality,” of any given right can be easily ridiculed by formulating a right at a very concrete level but the rhetorical force of such a ridicule disappears when we remember that these concrete formulations are instantiations of a more abstract right, as the dissenting judges in Bowers v. Hardwick announced in the opening passage of their dissent: this case is no more about “a fundamental right to engage in homosexual sodomy,” as the Court purports to declare, than Stanley v. Georgia was about a fundamental right to watch obscene movies, or Katz v. United States was about a fundamental right to place interstate bets from a telephone booth. Rather, this case is about “the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized men,” namely, ‘the right to be let alone,’ Bowers v. Hardwick 478 U.S. 186, 199 (1986) (Blackmun, J. dissenting) (citations omitted).

  23. 23.

    Its locus classicus is of course the second chapter of John Stuart Mill’s “On Liberty.” Perhaps the best-known modern judicial statement of this idea is the United States Supreme Court’s assertion that “[e]ven a false statement may be deemed to make a valuable contribution to public debate,” New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 255, 279 n. 19 (1964). A modified recent restatement of the theory may be found in Sunstein (1993).

  24. 24.

    See Meiklejohn (1948); see also Meiklejohn (1961).

  25. 25.

    See Schauer (1982, 7–10).

  26. 26.

    Dworkin (1978, 92).

  27. 27.

    As is clearly the case of Cooper and Williams (1999).

  28. 28.

    As Professor Troper concludes, with respect to the French loi Gayssot: “En punissant la négation du génocide des mêmes peines que l’incitation à la haine raciale, [le Parlement] présume qu’elle est une acte équivalent parce qu’il est de même nature et qu’il porte comme lui atteinte à des intérets qui doivent être protégés” (Troper 1999, 1252).

  29. 29.

    See Fox and Nolte (1995).

  30. 30.

    See e.g. Hart Ely (1980, 135–79).

  31. 31.

    See Waldron (1998, 280–81).

  32. 32.

    For an impressive statement and elaboration of the “comparative institutional” thesis, see in particular Komesar (1994).

  33. 33.

    There are also significant cultural factors. What is the dominant social expectation about certain types of people who are encouraged to stand for election, or to apply for nominations to certain bodies. These cultural expectations are of course, themselves, partly determined by institutional factors (what are the procedures and formal criteria for election or nomination).

References

  • Balkin, J., and S. Levinson. 2001. Understanding the constitutional revolution. Virginia Law Review 87: 1045–1109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. 2001. Culture and equality. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. 1969. Four essays on liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickel, A.M. 1975. The morality of consent. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassese, A. 1999. Ex injuria jus oritur: Are we moving towards international legitimation of forcible humanitarian countermeasures in the world community? European Journal of International Law 10: 23–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, J., and A.M. Williams. 1999. Hate speech, holocaust denial and international human rights law. European Human Rights Law Review 6: 593–613.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. 1983. Paternalism In Paternalism, ed. R. Sartorius. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1978. Taking rights seriously. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s empire. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 2002. Forked tongues, faked doctrines. Index Online. Available at: http://www.oneworld.org/index_oc/issue397/dworkin.htm. Visited 18 Apr 2002.

  • Elster, J. 1983. Sour grapes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1986. Harm to self: The moral limits of the criminal law, 3rd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrajoli, L. 1994. Dai diritti del cittadino ai diritti Della persona. In La cittadinanza Appartenenza, identità, diritti, ed. D. Zolo. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, G.H., and G. Nolte. 1995. Intolerant democracies. Harvard International Law Journal 36: 1–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardbaum, S. 1996. Liberalism, autonomy, and moral conflict. Stanford Law Review 48: 385–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Günther, K. 1999. The legacies of injustice and fear: A European approach to human rights and their effect on political culture. In The EU and human rights, ed. P. Alston. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G., and J.J. Thomson. 1996. Moral relativism and moral objectivity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart Ely, J. 1980. Democracy and distrust. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Komesar, N.K. 1994. Imperfect alternatives. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meiklejohn, A. 1948. Free speech and its relation to self-government. Port Washington: Kennikat Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meiklejohn, A. 1961. The first amendment is an absolute. Supreme Court Review 1961: 1–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meiland, J.W., and M. Krausz (eds.). 1982. Relativism, cognitive and moral. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 1997. Republicanism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 2001. A theory of freedom. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. 1974. The DeFunis case and the constitutionality of preferential treatment of racial minorities. Supreme Court Review 1974: 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1972. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1980. Kantian constructivism in moral theory. Journal of Philosophy 77: 515–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1993. The law of peoples. In On human rights: The oxford amnesty lectures, ed. S. Shute and S. Hurley, 41–82. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999. The law of peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski, W. 1990. Moral pluralism and legal neutrality. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski, W. 1996. The paradox of toleration. In Law, life and the images of man: Festschrift for Jan M. Broekman, ed. F. Fleerackers, E. van Leeuwen, and B. van Roermund, 377–389. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski, W. 1998. The concept of legal equality and an underlying theory of discrimination. Saint Louis-Warsaw Transatlantic Law Journal, 63–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski, W. 1999. Freedom of speech and its limits. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartorius, R. (ed.). 1983. Paternalism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. 1982. Free speech: A philosophical enquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, M.G., and R.L. Vojtovic. 2000. Holocaust denial and freedom of expression. In The jurisprudence of human rights law: A comparative interpretive approach, ed. T.S. Orlin, A. Rosas, and M. Scheinin, 133–158. Turku/Åbo: Åbo Akademi University, Institute for Human Rights.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C.R. 1986. Legal interference with private preferences. University of Chicago Law Review 53: 1129–1174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C.R. 1993. Democracy and the problem of free speech. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Economist. 25 July 1998. What would confucius say now?

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M.R. 2001. Whatever happened to ‘Asian Values’? Journal of Democracy 12: 154–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Troper, M. 1999. La loi Gayssot et la constitution. Annales 54: 1239–1255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. 1998. Precommitment and disagreement. In Constitutionalism: Philosophical foundations, ed. L. Alexander, 271–299. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. 1982. An inconsistent form of relativism. In Relativism, cognitive and moral, ed. J.W. Meiland and M. Krausz. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. 1985. Ethics and the limits of philosophy. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wojciech Sadurski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sadurski, W. (2012). “It All Depends”: The Universal and the Contingent in Human Rights. In: Corradetti, C. (eds) Philosophical Dimensions of Human Rights. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2376-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics