Skip to main content

The Metaphysics of Time

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Physical Systems

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 264))

  • 756 Accesses

Abstract

For the most part, contemporary philosophy of time is governed by the distinction between Presentism and Eternalism. In understanding the nature of time, the choice seems to be between a moving present and a frozen history, laid out along the time-line. According to Presentism, the only concrete time that exists is the present. Everything that was past no longer exists and that which is in the future is yet to happen. The present moment keeps “flowing,” so that every instant is followed by a new instant in which part of the future becomes the present and the present becomes past. One frequently distinguishes between the past, present and future based on the types of action that are available. It is not possible to influence the past; actions take place only in the present. The future is pregnant with possibilities that might or might not be realized, depending on what we do in the present. Thus, Presentism is presupposed whenever one forms plans for the future or allows for the possibility that things could have been otherwise than they are.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Putnam (1967); Rietdijk (1966, 1976); Maxwell (1985); Rea (1998); Savitt (2000); Sider (2001); Saunders (2002); Hales and Johnson (2003); Gibson and Pooley (2006); Petkov (2006).

  2. 2.

    I am here ignoring the distinction between perdurantists and endurantists, which may cause consternation for some metaphysicians of time. Perdurantists believe that objects are four-dimensional, and that the time-slices of an object form genuine parts of the object. Endurantists believe that objects are three-dimensional, and that these objects endure throughout time, with different properties instantiated in the object at different times. While eternalists are ordinarily perdurantists, it is certainly consistent for an eternalist to be an endurantist about objects, although this is not an easy position to hold. I will not go into this debate about the nature of objects, except to say that both perdurantists and endurantists take time-slices as the basic entities from which objects are comprised. Either one believes that an object is wholly present when a single time-slice is present (which makes the view endurantist), or one believes that the object is wholly present in virtue of all time-slices being present (which makes the view perdurantist). I am trying to undercut the distinction between endurantism and perdurantism as well, since I am suggesting that being present at t is not the same as existing.

  3. 3.

    See Bigelow (1996), Sider (1999) and Markosian (2004) for an attempt to defend Presentism against the problem of cross-temporal relations, and Davidson (2003) for a critique of such attempts.

  4. 4.

    This image of the present moving from one instant to the “next” may be seriously misleading, since the assumption is that the temporal dimension can be modeled by a real line. Since the instants along this line are dense, between any two temporal instants there is another. Thus, strictly speaking there is no single instant that can be designated as the “next” one, just as there is no single spatial point that is the next point to the right of the point marked 0. But one may speak loosely in this way to describe the movement of the now.

  5. 5.

    Mellor (1981) argues that it is possible to think of things evolving in time and their events as existing within a B-series. But Mellor is a B-theorist who wants to deny the existence of the A-series. See Dagys (2008) for further analysis.

  6. 6.

    See Smart (1949) for an examination of the problem of the rate of time’s flow. Smart argues that since it is not clear what rate time flows, it is not coherent to talk of the flow of time. See Markosian (1993) for an attempt to respond to Smart.

  7. 7.

    See Diekemper (2005) for an argument that a pure presentist position is inconsistent with the asymmetric fixity of the temporal order.

  8. 8.

    See Hinchliff (1996) for an attempt to resist the transitivity of the coexistence relation.

  9. 9.

    See Clifton and Hogarth (1995, pp. 382–83).

  10. 10.

    See Callender (2000) for an argument claiming that this definition of Presentism steers too far from our standard presentist intuition.

  11. 11.

    Sider, for example, argues that limiting existing events to a single spacetime point is extremely counterintuitive:

    … the presentist might banish all of space-time other than a single point. (A related proposal would be to banish all of spacetime other than a single point plus its past light cone.) Note that the right way to assert here-now-ism is to say that only a single point of the spacetime is real, that there exist no spatiotemporally distant events. The wrong way is to say that at any point in the spacetime, only a single point of spacetime is real. This suggests a misleading picture, that there are multiple points in spacetime, but somehow, from the perspective of one of them, the others are not real. Unless the presentist is involved in a Meinongian distinction between being and existence, this can only be a confusion. (Sider, 2001, p. 44)

    Sider’s argument is based on the assumption that the relation of coexistence must be either true or false. If spatiotemporally distant events do not coexist with the here-now, then they do not exist when the here-now exists. On the other hand, if one looks at spacetime from the perspective of the spatiotemporally distant event, then the distant event exists and the here-now does not. Is it reasonable to assume that existence depends on the perspective of the spatiotemporal point? Isn’t existence simply a brute fact independent of the particular perspective? Sider’s worry may be resisted by insisting that relations of coexistence are not well defined on space-like separated events. One way to avoid defining relations of coexistence is to restrict the predicate “being present” to a particular point on a particular worldline. According to this proposal, it is meaningless to ask whether space-like separated events on different worldlines coexist. While this solution feels a little strained, there is no way to reject it out of hand.

  12. 12.

    See Savitt (2000) for a critique of cone-Presentism.

  13. 13.

    See Hawley (2006) for a discussion on the various strategies of defending metaphysical claims from conflicts with scientific theories.

  14. 14.

    See, for example, Craig (2001b) and Hinchliff (2000) for such a line of argument.

  15. 15.

    Frisch (2009) argues that causality principles govern the derivation of dispersion relations for the electromagnetic field. This application of a causal principle seems to provide evidence that in the context of relativistic field theories, principles of causation are scientifically relevant. As Frisch points out, the relevance of causal principles in this limited context does not imply an a priori commitment to causal principles for all scientific theories, which is Norton’s main source of objection to fundamentalism about causation.

References

  • Bigelow, J. 1996. “Presentism and Properties.” Noûs 30:35–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. 2000. “Shedding Light on Time.” Philosophy of Science 67(Proceedings):S587–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clifton, R., and M. Hogarth. 1995. “The Definability of Objective Becoming in Minkowski Spacetime.” Synthese 103:355–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. L. 1998. “McTaggart’s Paradox and the Problem of Temporary Intrinsics.” Analysis 58(2):122–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. L. 2001a. “McTaggart’s Paradox and Temporal Solipsism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79(1):32–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. L. 2001b. Time and the Metaphysics of Relativity. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dagys, J. 2008. J. McTaggart and H. Mellor on time. Problemos: Mokslo darbai (Problems: Research Papers) 73:115–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, M. 2003. “Presentism and the Non-present.” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 113(1):77–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diekemper, J. 2005. “Presentism and Ontological Symmetry.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83(2):223–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. 2009. “ ‘The Most Sacred Tenet’? Causal Reasoning in Physics.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60:459–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, I., and O. Pooley. 2006. “Relativistic Persistance.” Philosophical Perspectives: Metaphysics 20:157–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, W. 1979. “Special Relativity and the Present.” Philosophical Studies 36:233–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hales, S. D., and T. A. Johnson. 2003. “Endurantism, Perdurantism and Special Relativity.” The Philosophical Quarterly 53:524–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. 2006. “Science as a Guide to Metaphysics?” Synthese: An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science 149(3):451–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinchliff, M. 1996. “The Puzzle of Change.” Noûs 30:119–36. Supplement: Philosophical Perspective, 10, Metaphysics, 1996.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinchliff, M. 2000. “A Defense of Presentism in a Relativistic Setting.” Philosophy of Science 67:S575–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. 1993. “How Fast Does Time Pass?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53(4):829–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. 2004. A Defense of Presentism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, N. 1985. “Are Probabilism and Special Relativity Incompatible?” Philosophy of Science 52(1):23–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart, J. E. 1908. “The Unreality of Time.” Mind 17(68):457–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. 1999. The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. Translated by I. B. Cohen and A. Whitman. California: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. 2003. “Causation as Folk Science.” Philosophers’ Imprint 3(4):1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. 2007. “Do Causal Principles Contradict Causal Anti-Fundamentalism?” In Thinking About Causes: From Greek Philosophy to Modern Physics, edited by P. K. Machamer and G. Wolters, 222–34. Pittsburgh, PA: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petkov, V. 2006. “Is There an Alternative to the Block Universe View?” In The Ontology of Spacetime. Vol. 1: Philosophy and Foundations of Physics, edited by D. Dieks, 207–28. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. 2003. “Changes in Events and Changes in Things.” In Papers on Tense and Time, edited by B. Hasle, P. Öhrström, and J. Copeland, New ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1967. “Time and Physical Geometry.” The Journal of Philosophy 64(8):240–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. C. 1998. “Temporal Parts Unmotivated.” The Philosophical Review 107:225–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietdijk, C. W. 1966. “A Rigorous Proof of Determinism Derived from the Special Theory of Relativity.” Philosophy of Science 33(4):341–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietdijk, C. W. 1976. “Special Relativity and Determinism.” Philosophy of Science 43(4):598–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S. 2002. “How Relativity Contradicts Presentism.” In Time, Reality and Experience, edited by C. Callender, 277–92. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Savitt, S. F. 2000. “There’s No Time Like the Present (in Minkowski Spacetime).” Philosophy of Science 67(Proceedings):S563–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. 1999. “Presentism and Ontological Commitment.” Journal of Philosophy 96(7):325–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. 2001. Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. 1949. “The River of Time.” Mind 58(232):483–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, H. 1968. “On Einstein-Minkowski Space-time.” The Journal of Philosophy 65(1):5–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, H. 1991. “On Relativity Theory and Openness of the Future.” Philosophy of Science 58, 147–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. 1981. Real Time. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ori Belkind .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Belkind, O. (2012). The Metaphysics of Time. In: Physical Systems. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 264. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2373-3_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics