Skip to main content

The Public Sphere

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
NGOs as Legitimate Partners of Corporations

Part of the book series: Issues in Business Ethics ((IBET,volume 36))

  • 729 Accesses

Abstract

The goal of this chapter is to find a conception of the public sphere which ascribes NGOs an important role as political actors, particularly in the postnational constellation and particularly vis-à-vis corporations. The term is again assessed from a liberal and a deliberative perspective. The liberal model defines the public sphere as the political sphere in which only questions of constitutional essentials and basic justice are discussed and decided. This relatively narrow conception excludes NGOs which promote claims that are not (yet) considered as matters of basic justice from assuming a meaningful role in the public sphere. In the postnational constellation the narrow liberal focus poses additional problems given the absence of a global constitution. The deliberative model, by contrast, conceives of the public sphere as a network of communications where rational will-formation is achieved. The public sphere is thus an emancipatory space where citizens are empowered and can create pressures for legitimization towards both, the state and the economy (i.e., corporations). Deliberative democracy can equally conceive of a public sphere on a transnational level because it defines political action not by the locus or the actors involved but by the discursive character of their interaction. As such it provides a valuable perspective for the interaction between NGOs and corporations in the postnational constellation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See also Benhabib (1992: 107) and Chapter 7 of this book.

  2. 2.

    See also Habermas (1996b: 359/360), Palazzo (2002: 57ff.), and Cortina (1995: 54).

  3. 3.

    Such a public sphere, untainted by power, can change the judgement of values and reasons that is dominated by different institutions like political parties, the mass media and interest groups, and filter such values and reasons critically (Habermas, 1990b: 32).

  4. 4.

    Similarly, Dryzek defines the public sphere as “the most important location for deliberation” (2001: 652).

  5. 5.

    As mentioned above, the nonpublic character of civil society contrasts with public political culture. Rawls further differentiates between the public-private and the public-nonpublic distinction (Rawls, 1993: 220); he avoids the former “because of the individualistic non-associational connotations of the word ‘private’” (Charney, 1998: 98). For Rawls “there is no such thing as private reason” (1993: 220).

  6. 6.

    Rawls would reject this interpretation. For him civil society belongs to the nonpublic sphere, not to the private sphere. However, the tripartite distinction between public (political), nonpublic (political) and private is hard to defend: how would we envision nonpublic politics? Nonpublic politics is irreconcilable with the notion of democratic politics. On Rawls’ problematic distinction between public and nonpublic uses of reason, see also McCarthy (1994: 50).

  7. 7.

    On the liberal model of the public sphere, see for example Charney (1998: 99ff.) or Weintraub (1997: 8ff.); for a critical perspective, see Benhabib (1992: 95ff.) and Habermas (1996a: 26ff.).

  8. 8.

    Other schools of thought offer a more differentiated view. In republicanism for example, the state and the market are not the only sources of social integration; instead, solidarity and the orientation to the common good offer a third source. This third source of social integration is meant to have an autonomous basis in civil society, independent of the state and the market (Habermas, 1996a: 21f.). There is thus a public sphere beyond the state-market dichotomy and making something public does not mean locating it in the legal sphere and its institutions.

  9. 9.

    See section “Three Contexts for NGOs as Representatives of Public Claims” (Chapter 2) of this book for different contexts of institutionalization in which NGOs operate.

  10. 10.

    Yet Rawls allows public reason to encompass new variations of conceptions of justice. He acknowledges that otherwise “the claims of groups or interests arising from social change might be repressed and fail to gain their appropriate political voice” (Rawls, 1997: 775).

  11. 11.

    More about this will be discussed together with the implications of the substantively constrained conception of public reason in the section “Implications of Restricting the Content of Public Reason” (Chapter 7).

  12. 12.

    Negative liberty can roughly be defined as the absence of obstacles, barriers or constraints. The distinction between positive and negative liberty goes back to Isaiah Berlin (1979).

  13. 13.

    See, for example, Archibugi and Held (1995), Held (1995), McGrew (1997), Archibugi (2000); for more sources, see Scheuerman (2002: 439).

  14. 14.

    Thus, the liberal model exhibits exclusionary tendencies. More about this will be said in Chapter 7.

  15. 15.

    On the insensitivity of the liberal approach to the importance of non-governmental discursive sources on a global scale, see Dryzek (2000: 115ff.).

  16. 16.

    On the roles of NGOs in international organizations see also Scholte (2004: 213ff.).

  17. 17.

    A strong notion of publics is also attractive for radical democrats; for them, weak publics are just “irrelevant epiphenomena or instruments of co-optation” (Fung, 2003b: 365). In contrast to radical democrats, this work starts from the assumption that the interaction between NGOs and corporations can be political, and democratic, without pertaining to a strong global public. My aim is not to promote a strong global public but rather to explore the democratic legitimacy of a weak global public (to which NGOs belong).

  18. 18.

    In his “principle of publicity”, posited in the second appendix to his work “Perpetual Peace”, Kant claims that “[all] actions relating to the right of other human beings are wrong if their maxim is incompatible with publicity” (Kant and Humphrey, 2003: 37). As we will later see, this implies that legitimacy is conferred through the public use of reason.

  19. 19.

    On the reasons why Habermas’ conception of civil society in deliberative democracy does not realize this emancipatory potential, see section “Two-Track Model of Deliberative Democracy” (Chapter 8).

  20. 20.

    Again, as with civil society, the public sphere is not considered to be a residual category which simply absorbs claims that are not attractive for the state or the market. The public sphere and civil society are both constitutive of a democratic society.

  21. 21.

    Examples for movements that formed in the course of such re-definition processes are the women’s movement, the peace movement, the ecology movement, and new ethnic identity movements. All these movements follow a similar logic. The liberal model leaves little room for thinking about the logic of social movements (Benhabib, 1992: 100).

  22. 22.

    More about the problem of requiring internal democratic structures will be said in the section on the constraints on public reason (in the section “Implications of Restricting the Content of Public Reason” (Chapter 7)).

  23. 23.

    It must be noted that this is only true if we conceive of deliberative democracy as a normative concept of leading public discourses, which implies a particular conception of legitimacy. If we perceive deliberation as a formal decision-making mechanism, the conditions that make deliberative democracy attractive in small-scale contexts seem to be absent in the international arena. This view of deliberative democracy as a collective decision-making mechanism hinges upon the possibility of face-to-face meetings which are of course inappropriate to most regional and national, and certainly to all global, decisions (Fung, 2003a: 52).

  24. 24.

    According to Bohman, a transnational or cosmopolitan public sphere, as he calls it, is created when at least two culturally rooted public spheres start to overlap and intersect (Bohman, 1999: 195). Moreover, a transnational public sphere “requires the development of a complex set of critical abilities and practices, which, however egalitarian and wide in scope, have certain entry requirements best fulfilled by participation in a particular background public culture” (Bohman, 1999: 187). According to him, a global public sphere requires the development and expansion of transnational civil society (Bohman, 1999: 195). But as Dryzek rightly points out, there is little lost by treating transnational civil society and transnational public spheres as covering similar territories (Dryzek, 2000: 130). Moreover, in this work, the public sphere and civil society are rather seen as mutually enabling than as one being dependent on the other.

References

  • Adloff, F. Zivilgesellschaft: Theorie und politische Praxis. Frankfurt a. M.: Campus Verlag, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archibugi, D. “Cosmopolitical Democracy”. New Left Review 4 (July/August) (2000): 137–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. “Deliberative Rationality and Models of Democratic Legitimacy”. Constellations: An International Journal of Critical & Democratic Theory 1 (1) (1994): 26–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, J. “Citizenship and Norms of Publicity: Wide Public Reason in Cosmopolitan Societies”. Political Theory 27 (2) (1999): 176–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunkhorst, H. “Globalizing Solidarity: The Destiny of Democratic Solidarity in the Times of Global Capitalism, Global Religion, and the Global Public”. Journal of Social Philosophy 38 (1) (2007): 93–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chandhoke, N. “The Limits of Global Civil Society”. In Global Civil Society 2002, edited by M. Glasius, M. Kaldor, and H. Anheier, 35–53. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandhoke, N. “How Global is Global Civil Society?” Journal of World-Systems Research XI (2) (2005): 355–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charney, E. “Political Liberalism, Deliberative Democracy, and the Public Sphere”. The American Political Science Review 92 (1) (1998): 97–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy”. In The Good Polity, edited by A. Hamlin and B. Petit, 17–34. New York et al.: Basil Blackwell, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. “Reflections on Habermas on Democracy”. Ratio Juris 12 (4) (1999a): 385–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J.L. “Trust, Voluntary Association and Workable Democracy: The Contemporary American Discourse of Civil Society. In Democracy and Trust, edited by M.E. Warren, 208–48. Cambridge (UK) et al.: Cambridge University Press, 1999b.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, A. “The General Public as the Locus of Ethics in Modern Society”. In Facing Public Interest: The Ethical Challenge to Business Policy and Corporate Communications, edited by P. Ulrich and C. Sarasin, 43–58. Dordrecht et al.: Kluwer, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. “Transnational Democracy”. Journal of Political Philosophy 7 (1) (1999): 30–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond. Liberals, Critics, Contestations. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. Deliberative Global Politics: Discourse and Democracy in a Divided World. Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. “The Rule of Reasons. Three Models of Deliberative Democracy”. Ratio Juris 14 (4) (2001): 345–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fung, A. “Deliberative Democracy and International Labor Standards”. Governance 16 (1) (2003a): 51–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fung, A. “Survey Article: Recipes for Public Spheres: Eight Institutional Design Choices and Their Consequences”. Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (3) (2003b): 338–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A., and D. Thompson. Why Deliberative Democracy? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. The Theory of Communicative Action. Volume 2: The Critique of Functionalist Reason. Cambridge, UK: Blackwell, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit: Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft, 1st ed. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 1990b.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. “Three Normative Models of Democracy”. In Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, edited by S. Benhabib, 21–30. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 1996b.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. “The Postnational Constellation”. In The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays, edited by J. Habermas, 58–112. Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. “Eine politische Verfassung für die pluralistische Weltgesellschaft?” In Zwischen Naturalismus und Religion. Philosophische Aufsätze, edited by J. Habermas, 324–66. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, D. Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance. Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendriks, C.M. “Integrated Deliberation: Reconciling Civil Society’s Dual Role in Deliberative Democracy”. Political Studies 54 (3) (2006): 486–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor, M., H. Anheier, and M. Glasius. “Global Civil Society in an Era of Regressive Globalisation”. In Global Civil Society 2003, edited by M. Kaldor, H. Anheier, and M. Glasius, 3–17. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” In Kant: Political Writings (Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought), edited by I. Kant, 54–60. Cambridge (UK) et al.: Cambridge University Press, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I., and T. Humphrey. To Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch. Indianapolis: Hackett, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manin, B. “On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation”. Political Theory 15 (3) (1987): 338–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martí, J.L. “The Epistemic Conception of Deliberative Democracy Defended. Reasons, Rightness and Equal Political Autonomy”. In Deliberative Democracy and Its Discontents, edited by S. Besson and J.L. Martí, 27–56. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, T. “Kantian Constructivism and Reconstructivism: Rawls and Habermas in Dialogue”. Ethics 105 (1) (1994): 44–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrew, A. The Transformation of Democracy? Globalization and Territorial Democracy? Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanz, P., and J. Steffek. “Global Governance, Participation and the Public Sphere”. Government and Opposition 39 (2) (2004): 314–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, J. “Modernization, Rights and Democratic Society: The Limits of Habermas’s Democratic Theory”. Res Publica 11 (2) (2005): 101–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palazzo, G. Die Mitte der Demokratie: über die Theorie deliberativer Demokratie von Jürgen Habermas. Baden-Baden: Nomos-Verlags-Gesellschaft, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. Political Liberalism. New York/Chichester: Columbia University Press, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”. The University of Chicago Law Review 64 (3) (1997): 765–807.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheuerman, W.E. “Cosmopolitan Democracy and the Rule of Law”. Ratio Juris 15 (4) (2002): 439–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholte, J.A. “Civil Society and Democratically Accountable Global Governance”. Government and Opposition 39 (2) (2004): 211–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, A.B. The Idea of Civil Society. New York, NY: Free Press, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D. “Democratic Theory and Global Society”. The Journal of Political Philosophy 7 (2) (1999): 111–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulrich, P. Integrative Economic Ethics. Foundations of a Civilized Market Economy. Cambridge (UK) et al.: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weintraub, J. Public and Private in Thought and Practice: Perspectives on a Grand Dichotomy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, N. “Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of Actually Existing Democracy”. Social Text (25/26) (1990): 56–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, N. “Transnationalizing the Public Sphere.” 2005. Accessed June 20, 2007. http://www.republicart.net/disc/publicum/fraser01_en.htm.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dorothea Baur .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Baur, D. (2012). The Public Sphere. In: NGOs as Legitimate Partners of Corporations. Issues in Business Ethics, vol 36. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2254-5_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics