Advertisement

Rights, Needs and Duties

  • Stefan RamaekersEmail author
  • Judith Suissa
Chapter
  • 1.6k Downloads
Part of the Contemporary Philosophies and Theories in Education book series (COPT, volume 4)

Abstract

In this chapter, we examine the theoretical framework offered by conceptual work on rights, needs, duties and obligations and its influence on the way discussions of parenting are framed within both academic and policy literature. We discuss the opposing philosophical position that the language of rights and duties is inappropriate in this context of personal relationships that are better conceptualized in terms of love, intimacy and trust. We show how neither of these positions captures the particular ethical demands and qualities of the parent–child relationship and how our account of the first-person perspective in effect cuts across this contrast. We also explore some recent initiatives to import contractual processes and ideas into parent–child relationships (e.g. the proposed ‘upbringing pledge’ in Flanders and similar suggestions in the UK)

Keywords

Liberal Theory Moral Intuition Authoritative Parenting Moral Question Philosophical Work 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Archard, D. (1993). Children: Rights and childhood. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Arneil, B. (2002). Becoming versus being: A critical analysis of the child in liberal theory. In D. Archard & C. MacLeod (Eds.), The moral and political status of children (pp. 70–94). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Brennan, S., & Noggle, R. (1997, Spring). The moral status of children: Children’s rights, parents’ rights, and family justice. Social Theory and Practice, 23(1), 1–26.Google Scholar
  4. Brighouse, H. (2002). What rights (if any) do children have? In D. Archard & C. MacLeod (Eds.), Themoral and political status of children (pp. 31–52). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brighouse, H., & McAvoy, P. (2010). Do children have any rights? In R. Bailey (Ed.), The philosophy of education, an introduction (pp. 74–85). London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  6. Brighouse, H., & Swift, A. (2006). Parents’ rights and the value of the family. Ethics, 117, 80–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Brighouse, H., & Swift, A. (2009). Legitimate parental partiality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 37(1), 43–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bristow, J. (2009). Standing up to supernanny. Exeter: Societas Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  9. Buber (1947). The education of character. In Between man and man (pp. 104–117). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  10. Cassidy, C. (2007). Thinking children. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  11. Clayton, M. (2006). Justice and legitimacy in upbringing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cohen, H. (1980). Equal rights for children. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  13. Diamond, C. (1996). Missing the adventure: Reply to Martha Nussbaum. In The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy and the mind (pp. 309–319). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Figes, K. (2002). The terrible teens: What every parent needs to know. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  15. Furedi, F. (2001). Paranoid parenting. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
  16. Gaita, R. (1998). A common humanity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. Grossman, D. (2010). To the end of the land. London: Jonathan Cape.Google Scholar
  18. Helm, B. (2010). Love, friendship, and the self: Intimacy, identification, and the social nature of persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Jeske, D. (2008). Rationality and moral theory: How intimacy generates reasons. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
  20. Lambeir, B., & Ramaekers, S. (2007). The terror of explicitness: Philosophical remarks on the idea of a parenting contract. Ethics and Education, 2(2), 95–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Layard, R., & Dunn, J. (2009). A good childhood; searching for values in a competitive age. London: The Children’s Society/Penguin.Google Scholar
  22. McEwan, I. (1997). The child in time. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
  23. Midgley, M. (1991). Rights talk will not sort out child abuse. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 8(1), 103–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Munoz-Darde, V. (1999). Is the family to be abolished then? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 37–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Noggle, R. (2002). Special agents: Children’s autonomy and parental authority. In D. Archard & C. MacLeod (Eds.), Themoral and political status of children (pp. 97–117). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Rosenfeld, A., & Wise, N. (2000). Hyper-parenting; are you hurting your child by trying too hard? New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
  27. Schoeman, F. (1980). Rights of children, rights of parents, and the moral basis of the family. Ethics, 91(1), 6–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Sunderland, M. (2006). The science of parenting: How today’s brain research can help you raise happy, emotionally balanced children. London: DK Publishing.Google Scholar
  29. Van Crombrugge, H. (2008). The upbringing pledge as a framework for the parent-child relationship. In H. Van Crombrugge et al. (Eds.), Shared pedagogical responsibility (pp. 5–15). Antwerp: Intersentia.Google Scholar
  30. Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. London: Fontana.Google Scholar
  31. Winnicott, D. W. (1964). The child, the family, and the outside world. Middlesex: Penguin.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Faculty of Psychology and Educational Sciences Laboratory for Education and SocietyKatholieke Universiteit LeuvenLeuvenBelgium
  2. 2.Faculty of Policy and Society Institute of EducationUniversity of LondonLondonUK

Personalised recommendations