Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 71))

  • 543 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter is organized as follows. In Sect. 2, I summarize the terms and concepts we have covered. In Sect. 3, we revisit the notion of justification, in regard to objects, causal relations and the principle of uniformity. In Sect. 4, we discuss the viability of skeptical realism. Finally, in Sect. 5, we discuss Hume’s skepticism in light of his conception of objects, where we briefly touch on Berkelian idealism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is not an exhaustive list of the different kinds of belief at work in Book I of the Treatise (see Falkenstein 1997 b, p. 40 for more kinds of belief). However, for our purposes, we need not discuss them all.

  2. 2.

    However, our ability to think in a natural, reflexive causal manner (where we do not believe in this relation; recall Chap. 2) does seem possible; see Sect. 3.2.1 of this chapter for more detail.

  3. 3.

    The bulk of this section was presented at the Upstate New York Workshop in Early Modern Philosophy, at Cornell University in 2008. I am grateful for the remarks given to me by my commentator, Alex Klein, and the audience.

  4. 4.

    In some respects, this anticipates Stove’s (1973) analysis of Hume. However, Stove argues that Hume was a closet “deductivist,” where Hume meant to show that any method that does not rely on a priori principles is worthless (see Millican 1995) for a comprehensive discussion (and dismissal) of Stove’s position). Husserl however, thought that Hume had no such noble intentions. Rather, Husserl thought that the Scotsman was just horribly mistaken, mired in a rather absurd methodological circle (see above).

  5. 5.

    Recall that Hume defines this principle in the Treatise as follows: “instances of which we have had no experience, must resemble those, of which we have had experience, and that the course of nature continues always uniformly the same” (T 1.3.6.4; SBN 89).

  6. 6.

    And so, we must reject Beauchamp and Rosenberg (1981), Arnold (1983), Broughton (1983) and Baier (1991). Cf. Garrett’s rejection (1997).

  7. 7.

    More precisely: Millican argues that inductive claims are not justified by a “faculty of intellectual insight” (1995, p. 211), but the “true foundation of such extrapolation is revealed to be animal instinct” (1995, p. 212). This means, Millican argues, that there is a looser sense in which inductive claims may be classified as “reasonable:” “Hume thus has the basis for a naturalistic account of his intermediate sense of ‘reason,’ according to which beliefs and methods of inference count as reasonable if they have a place within a consistent and systematic rule-governed framework dominated by the ‘permanent, irresistible, and universal’ principles of the imagination, and in particular by the fundamental belief in inductive uniformity and the rules by which to judge of causes and effects which systematize its implications. Hume can, of course, give no independent justification for this fundamental belief itself” (1995, p. 207). Similarly, Millican writes in 2002b:” Our beliefs about the behavior of objects in the external world, and the operations of our own mind, are founded on a naïve assumption of uniformity, a blind reliance on the past rather than on any sort of supernatural insight into why thinks work the way they do” (31). I show above, however, that our belief in the principle of uniformity does is in fact, seem to be justified, however implicitly. Strictly speaking, although our belief in the principle of uniformity is not rationally justified, it is not, as a result, “naïve” or “blind.” Rather, it is duly informed by the regularity that naturally obtains of our impressions, where that regularity is not be confused with a principle about the regularity (i.e. the principle of uniformity). See above for more detail.

  8. 8.

    Causal relations might also obtain of events. However, Hume never clearly distinguishes between events and objects in the Treatise.

  9. 9.

    Stroud writes: “[No] objective connection between perceptions or objects [is] required in order for me to come to think of things as causally connected with each other. As long as my experience exhibits certain regularities I will come to have that ‘fictitious’ idea” (p. 140, emphasis added).

  10. 10.

    In a footnote, in response to Loeb’s earlier work (1997, pp. 283–6), Owen (1999) argues that in these instances, Hume does not have what modern epistemologists mean by justification in mind. Owen writes: “In the early modern period, to explain something as the product of the faculty of reason was to explain the production of a state that we take to be true. It is natural enough for Hume to think that when he has explained the production of belief, he has explained the production of a state we take to be true, even though he denied that we were determined by reason. But this is a much weaker claim than modern claims about justification. Similar remarks apply to Hume’s frequent use of expressions such as ‘reason justly’ (T 72) and ‘just inference’ (T 89)” (p. 139, n. 38). However, if, on Hume’s account, we believe something to be true, to be real, we are, in some instances, engaged in a proper, i.e. justified belief production process, and in others, we are clearly not, i.e. all those instances where we come up with fantastic beliefs. Thus, Hume is doing more than simply explaining the production of a state we take to be true; he gives us an account that distinguishes between those states that we take to be true that are not justified, but are “occult” (e.g. believing in an immaterial soul) v. those that are. Also see Loeb’s 2002 response to Owen, p. 43, n 13.

  11. 11.

    In this respect, Hume may, generally speaking, be classified as what some call an “internalist,” i.e. as Bonjour (2010) puts it: “justification is internalist if an only if it requires that all of the factors needed for a belief to be epistemically justified for a given person be cognitively accessable to that person, internal to his cognitive perspective” (p. 364). However, an extensive discussion of internalism v. externalism would take us beyond the scope of this project.

  12. 12.

    There are many other New Humeans (e.g. Broughton; see Read and Richman 2007), but I cannot effectively address all of their positions here.

  13. 13.

    This article, “David Hume: Objects and Power,” reflects many of the ideas Strawson presented in his earlier book, The Secret Connexion: Causation, Realism and David Hume (1989). “Objects and Power” was initially published in 2001 in the first edition of Richman and Read’s The New Hume Debate.

  14. 14.

    Much of Strawson’s explanation concerns the Enquiry, which falls outside the scope of this book. However, to make his case concerning relative ideas, he relies heavily on a handful of passages from the Treatise. We focus on those here.

  15. 15.

    Kail writes regarding the New Humeans: “realists do not, and more importantly, need not, read Hume as believing in powers. Realists talk instead of Hume’s ‘assumption’ or his ‘taking for granted’ or his ‘supposition’ of powers. And when realists do talk of ‘belief’ the term is either uses in a sense not intended to respect technicalities of Hume’s own view of belief, or else appeals to the technical term ‘natural belief, a category which carries its own complications” (2007b, p. 254). However, Strawson does not give any kind of extensive definition of natural belief in this paper. Regardless, as we will see in our discussion of Kail (Sect. 4.1.2 above), “natural belief,” as it is articulated by Kail, is somewhat similar to my notion of transcendental belief.

  16. 16.

    It should be noted that Hume explicitly mentions relative ideas just once in the Treatise, at T 1.2.6.9; SBN 68. He indirectly refers to them one other time, at T 1.4.5.19; SBN 241, and once in the Enquiry, EHU 7.29; SBN 76–7.

  17. 17.

    Not quite the same since these ideas do not exactly represent impressions, but Hume acknowledges this issue on the next page of the Treatise. See below for more detail.

  18. 18.

    Also see Wright (2007, p. 90) who relies heavily on T 1.4.5.20; SBN 241. Like Strawson, Wright’s distinction between supposing and conceiving is, I think, mistaken; he neglects to see that it reflects Hume’s distinction between fantastic ideas and ideas that have content. Concomitantly, like Strawson, Wright ignores the complex psychological account of justifiably imagining objects that has been explicated in Parts II and III of this book. Thus, Wright’s account of objects must also be rejected.

  19. 19.

    As explained in Chap. 2, we do have an impression of necessity. However, it is an impression of reflexion, which is merely a habituated reflex to “pass from an object to the idea of its usual attendant” (T 1.3.14.22; SBN 165–6).

  20. 20.

    As is the case with Strawson, Wright’s first premise in his argument to show that Hume thought that mind-independent causality (i.e. Causality) exists is: We may “suppose” that mind-independent objects exist, where such objects do not represent (indirectly or not) impressions. Nevertheless, these ideas refer to mind-independent objects. Thus, because we can “suppose” content-less ideas of objects that refer to mind-independent objects, we may also “suppose” content-less ideas of Causality that refer to mind-independent causal relations. Note: “It is clear then that at least in his discussion of external existence, Hume argues that we are not limited in our beliefs about objects to what is based on our legitimate impression-derived ideas. The same then is to be found in his discussion of space and time in Part 2, Book I of the Treatise. Why should there be an exception in the case of Hume’s discussion of causality?” (2007, p. 90). However, as we have seen, this is not the case. When Hume uses the word ‘suppose’ in the passages that Strawson and Wright rely on to make their case, he is referring to an unjustified act of the imagination, e.g. cases where we imagine substances and souls. But these ideas do not refer to anything; Hume does not think that such things actually exist. As far as our justified ideas of objects are concerned, we must imagine an idea of an object that indirectly represents an impression (and in fact, this is also the case in regard to our ideas of space and time; they are abstract ideas; recall Chap. 7. Thus, we may deny Wright’s first premise as well, and thus, effectively undermine his argument that Hume thought that there are content-less ideas that refer to mind-independent causal relations.

  21. 21.

    Cf. Millican (2009), who takes a different, anti-realist approach to Kail’s work, particularly Kail (2007b).

  22. 22.

    Also recall Chap. 4, Sect. 3 of this book, where we saw that according to Hume, to conceive of is, indeed, to ontologically commit to, but only in terms of de dicto existence.

References

  • Arnold, N. S. (1983). Hume’s skepticism about inductive inferences. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 21(1), 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1973). The central questions of philosophy. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier, A. (1991). A progress of sentiments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxter, D. (2008). Hume’s difficulty. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T., & Rosenberg, A. (1981). Hume and the problem of causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1948–1957). The works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne. In A. A. Luce & T. E. Jessop (Eds.), A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons. abbreviated as PHK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonjour, L. (2010). Externalism/internalism. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (2nd ed., pp. 364–8). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broughton, J. (1983). Hume’s skepticism about causal inferences. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64(1), 3–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • DePierris, G. (2002). Causation as a philosophical relation in Hume. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64(3), 499–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falkenstein, L. (1997a). Hume on manners of disposition and the ideas of space and time. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 79(2), 179–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falkenstein, L. (1997b). Naturalism, normativity, and scepticism in Hume’s account of belief. Hume Studies, 23(1), 29–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1986). David Hume: Philosopher of moral science. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, D. (1997). Cognition and commitment in Hume’s philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaskin, J. C. A. (1974). God, Hume and natural belief. Philosophy, 49, 281–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature (2nd ed.), (L.A. Selby-Bigge ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press; abbreviated as SBN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (2002). A treatise of human nature (D. F Norton & M. J. Norton ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press; abbreviated as T.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenology (D. Carr, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press; abbreviated as C.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). Logical investigations (J. N. Findlay, Trans.). New York: Humanities Press; abbreviated as LI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1980). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and a phenomenological philosophy (1st book F. Kersten, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff; abbreviated as I1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kail, P. J. E. (2001). Projection and necessity in Hume. European Journal of Philosophy, 9(1), 24–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kail, P. J. E. (2007a). Projection and realism in Hume’s philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kail, P.J.E. (2007b). How to understand Hume’s realism. In: R. Read & K. Richman (Eds.), The new Hume debate (revised ed., pp. 253–269). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, A. (2008). Response to Stefanie Rocknak: Naturalistic pre-theoretical belief in Book I of Hume’s treatise. Comments presented at the Upstate New York Early Modern Workshop, Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loeb, L. E. (2002). Stability and justification in Hume’s treatise. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (1995). Hume’s Argument concerning induction: Structure and interpretation. In D. Owen (Ed.), Hume: General philosophy (2000) (Vol. 2, pp. 165–218). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (2002b). Context, aims, structure of the enquiry. In P. Millican (Ed.), Reading Hume on human understanding (pp. 27–66). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (2002c). Hume’s Sceptical doubts concerning induction. In P. Millican (Ed.), Reading Hume on human understanding (pp. 107–74). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (2009). Hume, causal realism, and causal science. Mind, 118(471), 648–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrisroe, M. (1973). Did Hume read Berkeley? a conclusive answer. Philological Quarterly, 52(2), 310–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossner, E. C. (1980). The life of David Hume (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mounce, H. O. (1999). Hume’s naturalism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen, D. (1999). Hume’s reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Passmore, J. (1968). Hume’s intentions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popkin, R. H. (1980). The high road to pyrrhonism. San Diego, CA: Austen Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. H. (1940). Hume’s theory of the external world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, R., & Richman, K. (Eds.). (2007). The new Hume debate (revised ed.). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser, E. (2007). Two definitions of ‘cause’, Newton and the significance of the humean distinction between natural and philosophical relations. The Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 5(1), 83–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. K. (1941). The philosophy of David Hume; a critical study of its origins and central doctrines. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stove, D. C. (1973). Probability and Hume’s inductive skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1952). Introduction to logical theory. London: Methuen and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1989). The secret connexion: Causation, realism and David Hume. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2007). David Hume: Objects and power. In:R. Read & K. Richman (Eds.), In The new Hume debate (revised ed., pp. 31–51). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (1977). Hume. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (2000). The quest for reality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waxman, W. (1994). Hume’s theory of consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilbanks, J. (1968). Hume’s theory of imagination. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winkler, K. (2007). The new Hume. In R. Read & K. Richman (Eds.), The new Hume debate (revised ed., pp. 52–87). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolhouse, R. (1988). The empiricists. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, J. P. (1983). The skeptical realism of David Hume. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, J. P. (2007). Hume’s causal realism: Recovering a traditional interpretation. In R. Read & K. Richman (Eds.), The new Hume debate (revised ed., pp. 88–99). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rocknak, S. (2013). Conclusion. In: Imagined Causes: Hume's Conception of Objects. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 71. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2187-6_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics