Skip to main content

“Explanation,” Philosophy and Theory in Health Inequalities Research: Towards a Critical Realist Approach

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Rethinking Social Epidemiology

Abstract

The relative lack of attention to philosophy and theory in research on social inequalities in health and its consequences for explanation and methodology has been described in the social epidemiologic literature. Nevertheless, the field of social epidemiology, dominated as it is by the trappings of positivism, is arguably still in need of further development of epistemological frameworks that can adequately incorporate richer explanations of the phenomena we study. Some have advocated for the adoption of a critical realist perspective for the study of social inequalities in health in order to overcome some of the difficulties described above. This chapter uses critical realism as a means to identify some of the epistemological and methodological difficulties inherent in attempts to explain health inequalities (especially the connection between social and biological mechanisms) and offer an “affirmative” approach to health inequalities research based on the insights of ­critical realist philosophy. In both the physical and social sciences, concerns about epistemology and philosophy are routinely left unexamined. This chapter argues that a more explicit engagement with such questions is an important next step in social epidemiology and health inequalities research. The chapter begins with a description of the explanatory problem faced by research on social inequalities in health. This explanatory task is difficult, but it is precisely that difficulty which ­cannot be adequately accommodated by the unacknowledged epistemological underpinnings of social epidemiology. The chapter highlights several key features of the critical realist approach and demonstrates how these can be usefully applied to health inequalities research to solve persistent problems of explanation and ­methodological pluralism. Specifically, the chapter argues that the complexity of the social phenomena implicated in this research demands a more detailed consideration of what is meant by causation, “explanation” and “theory,” and of what the relationship of these concepts should be to empirical research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are, of course, some examples of works that have been at least partly successful at mounting social explanations, including the work of Kawachi and others on social capital (Kawachi et al. 1997, 2004; Kawachi 1999), Wilkinson (1996) with regards to social capital and other psychosocial factors, Hertzman and Marmot’s (1996) explanations of the health consequences of rapid economic change in central and eastern Europe, and the work of a number of authors offering sociopolitical explanations (e.g., Navarro et al. 2006; Bambra et al. 2009).

  2. 2.

    Link and Phelan’s (1995) work on “fundamental causes” is a step in the right direction of deeper explanations, but I argue that the emphasis on social conditions and socioeconomic position is not fundamental enough, as its explanatory focus is situated primarily at the level of events (as opposed to mechanisms and structures – see Fig. 2.1) and it is not successful in distinguishing between necessary and contingent relations.

  3. 3.

    Indeed, one of the criticisms of realism when people started writing about it in the social sciences is that many said “we’re all realists now” (Cloke et al. 1991). Essentially, it codified the way many social scientists already worked. Even if this critique of unoriginality is valid, it is certainly advantageous that social scientists practice their craft in a way that is self-consciously aware of the philosophical underpinnings, and there is still plenty of relatively superficial analysis that could benefit from the insights of realist philosophy.

References

  • Bambra C, Pope D, Swami V et al (2009) Gender, health inequalities and welfare state regimes: a cross-national study of thirteen European countries. J Epidemiol Community Health 63:38–44

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar R (1975) A realist theory of science. Leeds Books, Leeds

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar R (1979a) The possibility of naturalism. Harvester, Brighton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar R (1979b) On the possibility of social scientific knowledge and the limits of naturalism. In: Mepham J, Ruben D-H (eds) Issues in Marxist philosophy, vol 3, Epistemology, science, ideology. Humanities Press, Atlantic Highlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar R (1989) Reclaiming reality. Verso, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryman A (1988) Quantity and quality in social research. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ciaffa JA (1998) Max Weber and the problems of value-free social science: a critical examination of the Werturteilsstreit. Bucknell University Press, Lewisburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Cloke P, Philo C, Sadler D (1991) Approaching human geography: an introduction to contemporary theoretical debates. Guildford Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn JR (2006) Speaking theoretically about population health: commentary on carpiano RM and daley DM “A guide and glossary on theory-building for population health”. J Epidemiology & Community Health 60:572–573

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbes A, Wainwright SP (2001) On the methodological, theoretical and philosophical context of health inequalities research: a critique. Soc Sci Med 53:801–816

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Gartell CD, Gartell JW (1996) Positivism in sociological practice: 1967–1990. Can Rev Sociol 33:143–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halfpenny P (1982) Positivism and sociology: explaining social science. Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré R (1979) Social being: a theory for social psychology. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertzman C, Marmot M (1996) The leading hypothesis and its discontents: a synthesis of evidence and outstanding issues regarding the east-west life expectancy gap. In: Hertzman C, Kelly S, Bobak M (eds) East-West life expectancy gap in Europe. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertzman C, Weins M (1996) Child development and long-term outcomes: a population health perspective and summary of successful interventions. Soc Sci Med 43:1083–1095

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hunter M (2007) The changing political economy of sex in South Africa: the significance of unemployment and inequalities to the scale of the AIDS pandemic. Soc Sci Med 64:689–700

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kawachi I (1999) Social capital and community effects on population and individual health. Ann NY Acad Sci 896:120–130

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kawachi I, Kennedy BP, Lochner K et al (1997) Social capital, income inequality, and mortality. Am J Public Health 87:1491–1498

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kawachi I, Kim D, Coutts A et al (2004) Commentary: reconciling the three accounts of social capital. Int J Epidemiol 33:682–690

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Keat R (1981) The politics of social theory: Habermas, Freud, and the critique of positivism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Krieger N (1994) Epidemiology and the web of causation: has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med 39:887–903

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Krieger N (1999) Embodying inequality: a review of concepts, measures, and methods for ­studying health consequences of discrimination. Int J Health Serv 29:295–352

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Krieger N (2001) Theories for social epidemiology in the 21st century: an ecosocial perspective. Int J Epidemiol 30:668–677

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Link B, Phelan J (1995) Social conditions as fundamental causes of disease. J Health Soc Behav 35:80–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muntaner C (2004) Commentary: social capital, social class, and the slow progress of psychosocial epidemiology. Int J Epidemiol 33:674–680

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Navarro V, Muntaner C, Borrell C et al (2006) Politics and health outcomes. Lancet 368:1033–1037

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Oakes JM (2004) The (mis)estimation of neighborhood effects: causal inference for a practicable social epidemiology. Soc Sci Med 58:1929–1952

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pawson R (1989) A measure for measures: a manifesto for empirical sociology. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose G (1985) Sick individuals and sick populations. Int J Epidemiol 14:32–38

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Sayer A (1992) Method in social science: a realist approach, 2nd edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayer A (1993) Postmodernist thought in geography: a realist view. Antipode 25:320–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sayer A (1997) Essentialism, social constructionism, and beyond. Sociol Rev 45:453–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shonkoff J, Phillips DA (eds) (2000) From neurons to neighbourhoods: the science of early child development. National Research Council and Institute of Medicine, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarlov AR (1996) Social determinants of health: the sociobiological translation. In: Blane D, Brunner E, Wilkinson R (eds) Health and social organization: towards a health policy for the 21st century. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor SE, Repetti RL, Seeman T (1997) Health psychology: what is an unhealthy environment and how does it get under the skin? Annu Rev Psychol 48:411–47

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wainwright SP, Forbes A (2000) Philosophical problems with social research on health inequalities. Health Care Anal 8:259–277

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson RG (1994) The epidemiological transition: from material scarcity to social disadvantage? Daedalus 123:61–78

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson RG (1996) Unhealthy societies: the afflictions of inequality. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James R. Dunn .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dunn, J.R. (2012). “Explanation,” Philosophy and Theory in Health Inequalities Research: Towards a Critical Realist Approach. In: O’Campo, P., Dunn, J. (eds) Rethinking Social Epidemiology. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2138-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics