Skip to main content

Why Proof? A Historian’s Perspective

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Proof and Proving in Mathematics Education

Part of the book series: New ICMI Study Series ((NISS,volume 15))

Abstract

The history of mathematics provides evidence that proofs let mathematicians distinguish between true results and merely plausible ones; that the careful formulation of arguments allows them to see how individual mathematical results relate to broader mathematical ideas; and that the process of proving teaches logical reasoning. This paper presents key historical examples, including the origin of logical proof in Greek geometry, Aristotle’s proof-based model for science, the classical uses of visual demonstration, the developing power of abstraction and symbolism, the role of the principles of optimisation and symmetry, the changing standards of rigour between the algorithmic calculus of the eighteenth century and the proof-based version of the nineteenth, the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry, the modern reciprocal influences between philosophy and proof-based mathematics, and the current importance to society of understanding logic. We conclude that observing and teaching this history also helps us teach proof and proving.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Since the Babylonians used fractions with a base of 60, a practice which, incidentally, is the origin of our base-60 divisions of time into minutes and seconds, it would be more accurate to say that the area calculation given is equivalent to approximating π as 3  +  7/60  +  30/602.

  2. 2.

    None of the present discussion is meant to rule out the possibility that there were already steps towards forming axioms and logical proofs in Egyptian and Babylonian mathematics. No evidence of this is known to me at the present time, but scholarship on ancient mathematics continues, and one should keep an open mind. Even should such evidence be found, though, we would still need to explain why the Greeks chose to make logical proofs, using the smallest possible set of axioms, so central to their mathematics.

  3. 3.

    I have used the phrase ‘Greek proofs by contradiction’. In philosophy, proof by contradiction exists in cultures independent of the Greek, notably in China (Leslie 1964; Siu 2009). But as far as I know, only the Greeks and their mathematical heirs used it within mathematics; Professor Siu (2009) says that he does not know of an example from China before the coming of the Jesuits in the seventeenth century.

  4. 4.

    Vieta, and many mathematicians in the century following him, thought of expressions like x3 as volumes, x2 as areas, and x as lines, and so they would not write an expression like ax2+  bx  +  c. Vieta also designated his unknowns by upper-case vowels and his constants by upper-case consonants; the use of the lower-case letters x and y for the principal unknowns was introduced later by Descartes. But these details do not affect the main point here.

  5. 5.

    ‘If a straight line falling on two straight lines makes the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, then the two straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that side where the angles are less than two right angles’ (Euclid 1956, Postulate 5, p. 155; Fauvel and Gray 1987, p. 101).

  6. 6.

    If one wants to read only one history of mathematics, I recommend Katz (2009). For further readings, Katz’s bibliography will take one as far as one would like. Another good scholarly general history is Boyer and Merzbach (1989).

    For a collection of original sources in the history of mathematics from the period between 1200 and 1800, with excellent commentary, I recommend Struik (1969). Another fine collection of original sources, with shorter excerpts and commentary but covering the entire period from antiquity to the twentieth century, is Fauvel and Gray (1987). Original sources from Egypt, Babylon, China, India and the Islamic world may be found in Katz (2007), and, in classical analysis, in Birkhoff (1973). In this paper, I have given references to these four source books whenever relevant materials are accessible there. Finally, I highly recommend the Mathematical Association of America’s online ‘magazine’ Convergence (http://mathdl.maa.org/mathDL/46/) dedicated to the history of mathematics and its use in teaching. Besides articles, Convergence includes book reviews, translations of original sources, quotations about mathematics, portraits, ‘mathematics in the news’, and a great deal more.

References

  • Aristotle (1994). Posterior analytics [4th century BCE] (J. Barnes, Trans.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barzun, J. (1945). Teacher in America. London: Little-Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berggren, J. L. (1986). Episodes in the mathematics of medieval Islam. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berggren, J. L. (2007). Mathematics in medieval Islam. In V. J. Katz (Ed.), The mathematics of Egypt, Mesopotamia, China, India, and Islam: A sourcebook (pp. 515–675). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1951). The analyst, or a discourse addressed to an infidel mathematician [1734]. In A. A. Luce & T. R. Jessop (Eds.), The works of George Berkeley (Vol. 4, pp. 65–102). London: T. Nelson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birkhoff, G. (Ed.). (1973). A source book in classical analysis. With the assistance of Uta Merzbach. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano, B. (1817). Rein analytischer Beweis des Lehrsatzes dass zwischen je zwey [sic] Werthen, die ein entgegengesetztes Resultat gewaehren, wenigstens eine reele Wurzel der Gleichung liege. Prague: Gottlieb Haase. English translation in Russ, S. B. (1980). A translation of Bolzano’s paper on the intermediate value theorem. Historia Mathematica 7 (pp. 156–185). Also in Russ, S. B. (Ed.). (2004) The mathematical works of Bernard Bolzano (pp. 251–278). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonola, R. (1955). Non-Euclidean geometry: A critical and historical study of its development. With a Supplement containing “the theory of parallels” by Nicholas Lobachevski and “the science of absolute space” by John Bolyai. [1912] (H. S. Carslow, Trans.). New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, C. (1959). The history of the calculus and its conceptual development. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, C., & Merzbach, U. (1989). A history of mathematics (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cauchy, A.-L. (1821). Cours d’analyse de l’école royale polytechnique. 1re partie: Analyse algébrique [all that was published]. Paris: Imprimerie royale. In A.-L. Cauchy, Oeuvres (Series 2, Vol. 3)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cauchy, A.-L. (1823). Résumé des leçons données a l’école royale polytechnique sur le calcul infinitésimal. In A.-L. Cauchy (Ed.), Oeuvres (Series 2, Vol. 4, pp. 5–261). Paris: Imprimérie royale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, I. B. (1995). Science and the founding fathers. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Convergence (n. d.). [The Mathematical Association of America’s online magazine on the history of mathematics and its uses in the classroom.]. http://mathdl.maa.org/mathDL/46/

  • Dauben, J. (1978). Georg Cantor. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dauben, J. (2007). Chinese mathematics. In V. J. Katz (Ed.), The mathematics of Egypt, Mesopotamia, China, India, and Islam: A sourcebook (pp. 187–385). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Alembert, J., & de la Chapelle, J.-B. (1789). Limite. In J. d’Alembert, C. Bossut, & J. J. de Lalande (Eds.), Dictionnaire encyclopédique des mathématiques. Paris: Hotel de Thou.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dedekind, R. (1963). Essays on the theory of numbers. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunham, W. (1999). Euler: The master of us all. Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Euclid (1956). In T. L. Heath (Ed.), The thirteen books of Euclid’s elements. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Euler, L. (1748). Introductio in analysin infinitorum, Lausanne: Bousquet. In Euler Opera omnia (Series 1, Vols. 8–9). [English translation by John Blanton, as Leonhard Euler, Introduction to the Analysis of the Infinite in 2 Vols.]. New York et al: Springer, 1988–1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fauvel, J., & Gray, J. (Eds.). (1987). The history of mathematics: A reader. London: Macmillan, in Association with the Open University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabiner, J. V. (1981). The origins of Cauchy’s rigorous calculus. Cambridge: MIT Press. Reprinted New York: Dover, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabiner, J. V. (1990). The Calculus as Algebra: J.-L. Lagrange, 1736–1813. New York and London: Garland Publishing, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabiner, J. V. (1997). Was Newton’s calculus a dead end? The continental influence of Maclaurin’s Treatise of Fluxions. The American Mathematical Monthly, 104, 393–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grabiner, J. V. (2009). Why did Lagrange “prove” the parallel postulate? The American Mathematical Monthly, 116, 3–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J. (1989). Ideas of space: Euclidean, Non-Euclidean and relativistic (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hankins, T. L. (1976). Algebra as pure time: William Rowan Hamilton and the foundations of algebra. In P. Machamer & R. Turnbull (Eds.), Motion and time, space and matter (pp. 327–359). Columbus: Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Imhausen, A. (2007). Egyptian mathematics. In V. J. Katz (Ed.), The mathematics of Egypt, Mesopotamia, China, India, and Islam: A sourcebook (pp. 7–56). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jefferson, T. (1776). The declaration of independence. Often reprinted, e.g., T. Jefferson, The declaration of independence. Introduction by M. Hardt; additional material by G. Kindervater. London: Verso, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, V. J. (Ed.). (2007). The mathematics of Egypt, Mesopotamia, China, India, and Islam: A sourcebook. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, V. J. (2009). A history of mathematics: An introduction (3rd ed.). Boston: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knorr, W. (1993). The ancient tradition of geometric problems. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, A. (1957). From the closed world to the infinite universe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagrange, J.-L. (1759). Letter to Leonhard Euler, 24 November 1759, reprinted in Lagrange (1973), vol. XIV, pp. 170–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagrange, J.-L. (1770). Réflexions sur la resolution algébrique des équations. Nouveaux mémoires de l’Académie des sciences de Berlin. Reprinted in J.-L. Lagrange, Oeuvres (Vol. 3, pp. 205–424).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagrange, J.-L. (1797). Théorie des fonctions analytiques. Paris: Imprimerie de la République. An V [1797]. 2nd ed. Paris: Courcier, 1813. Reprinted as J.-L. Lagrange, Oeuvres (Vol. 9).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagrange, J.-L. (1808). Traité de la résolution des équations numériques de tous les degrés, avec des notes sur plusieurs points de la théorie des équations algébriques; Paris: Courcier. Reprinted in Oeuvres de Lagrange, vol. VIII (Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1879).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, D. (1964). Argument by contradiction in Pre-Buddhist Chinese reasoning. Canberra: Australian National University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). Adversaries and authorities: Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, C. (1742). A treatise of fluxions in two books. Edinburgh: T. Ruddimans.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKirahan, R. D., Jr. (1992). Principles and proofs: Aristotle’s theory of demonstrative science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1967). Universal Arithmetick [1728]. In D. T. Whiteside (Ed.), Mathematical works of Newton (Vol. 2, pp. 3–134). New York: Johnson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1995). The principia: Mathematical principles of natural philosophy [1687] (I. B. Cohen & A. Whitman, Trans.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfloker, K. (2007). Mathematics in India. In V. J. Katz (Ed.), The mathematics of Egypt, Mesopotamia, China, India, and Islam: A sourcebook (pp. 385–514). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato (2004). Plato’s Meno [4th century BCE] (G. Anastaplo & L. Berns, Trans.). Newburyport: Focus Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robson, E. (2007). Mesopotamian mathematics. In V. J. Katz (Ed.), The mathematics of Egypt, Mesopotamia, China, India, and Islam: A sourcebook (pp. 56–186). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1937). A critical exposition of the philosophy of Leibniz. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sageng, E. (2005). 1742: Colin MacLaurin, a treatise of fluxions. In I. Grattan-Guinness (Ed.), Landmark writings in western mathematics, 1640–1940 (pp. 143–158). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Siu, M. K. (2009, May 15). Plenary Panel presentation given at ICMI-19, Taiwan Normal University, Taipei.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1953). Ethics [1675]. J. Gutmann (Ed.). New York: Hafner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stedall, J. A. (Ed.). (2003). The greate invention of algebra: Thomas Harriot’s treatise on equations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Struik, D. J. (Ed.). (1969). A source book in mathematics, 1200–1800. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viète, F. (Vieta) (1968). Introduction to the analytic art (J. W. Smith, Trans.). In J. Klein (Ed.), Greek mathematical thought and the origin of Algebra. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Judith V. Grabiner .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Open Access This chapter is licensed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence and indicate if changes were made.

The images or other third party material in this chapter are included in the chapter's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the chapter's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder.

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Grabiner, J.V. (2012). Why Proof? A Historian’s Perspective. In: Hanna, G., de Villiers, M. (eds) Proof and Proving in Mathematics Education. New ICMI Study Series, vol 15. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2129-6_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics