Advertisement

Please Drink Responsibly: Can the Responsibility of Intoxicated Offenders Be Justified by the Tracing Principle?

  • Susan DimockEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy book series (LOET, volume 27)

Abstract

Normally, reduced mental capacities are thought to reduce responsibility. This is how, for example, the criminal defences of insanity/mental defect and automatism work. Persons who lack the capacity, due to a disease of the mind, to understand the nature of their actions or that they are wrong, and persons who lack the capacity for voluntary control of their bodily movements, are thought to lack essential capacities for criminal responsibility. These criminal law practices exemplify the intuition that responsibility tracks capacity, a view sometimes called “capacitarianism”. An equally widely held view, however, operates to restrict the commitment to capacitarianism: the intuition that when a person is responsible for his own reduced mental capacities, the exculpatory value of those reduced capacities is discounted or even extinguished. The paradigmatic case of such reduced capacities involves persons who have reduced their capacities (of understanding, foresight, knowledge, advertence or self-control) through voluntary intoxication. This intuition is also reflected in the criminal law practices of most jurisdictions. Whether such practices can be justified is the topic of this paper. My conclusion will be that, even if we accept the capacitarian intuition and its limited application to those who are responsible for their own reduced capacities, the legal instantiation of them in criminal practice is unjustified. My argument is that our treatment of intoxicated offenders is not, in fact, supported by these commitments, contrary to what many theorists and jurists think.

Keywords

Reasonable Doubt Criminal Liability Substitution Rule Fault Element Model Penal Code 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Alexander, Larry. 1990. “Reconsidering the Relationship Among Voluntary Acts, Strict Liability, and Negligence in Criminal Law.” Social Philosophy & Policy 7:84–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Colvin, Eric. 1981. “A Theory of the Intoxication Defense.” Canadian Bar Review 59:750–79.Google Scholar
  3. Criminal Code of Canada, s. 33.1 (2).Google Scholar
  4. Dimock, Susan. 2009. “The Responsibility of Intoxicated Offenders.” Journal of Value Inquiry 43:339–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Dressler, Joshua. 2006. Understanding Criminal Law. 4th ed. New York: Lexis.Google Scholar
  6. Duff, R.A. 2007. Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
  7. Duff, R.A. 2009. “Strict Responsibility, Moral and Criminal.” Journal of Value Inquiry 43:295–313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Fischer, John Martin and Mark Ravizza. 1988. Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Gardner, John. 2007. Offences and Defenses. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gough, Stephen. 1996. “Intoxication and Criminal Liability: The Law Commission’s Proposed Reforms.” Law Quarterly Review 112:335–55.Google Scholar
  11. Horder, Jeremy. 2004. Excusing Crime. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. McCord, David. 1990. “The English and American History of Voluntary Intoxication to Negate Mens Rea.” The Journal of Legal History 11:372–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Mitchell, Chester N. 1988. “The Intoxicated Offender — Refuting the Legal and Medical Myths.” International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 11:77–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Quigley, Tim. 1987a. “Specific and General Nonsense?” Dalhousie Law Journal 11:75–125.Google Scholar
  15. Quigley, Tim. 1987b. “A Shorn Beard.” Dalhousie Law Review 12:167–94.Google Scholar
  16. Quigley, Tim. 1987c. “Reform of the Intoxication Defense.” McGill Law Journal 33:1–48.Google Scholar
  17. Tadros, Victor. 2005. Criminal Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Tadros, Victor. 2009. “Poverty and Criminal Responsibility.” Journal of Value Inquiry 43:391–413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Cases

  1. D.P.P. v. Beard [1920] 14 Cr. App. R. 159 (HL)Google Scholar
  2. D.P.P. v. Majewski [1976] 2 All E.R. 142 (HL)Google Scholar
  3. Leary v. The Queen [1978] 1 S.C.R. 29Google Scholar
  4. R. v. Brenton [1999] 28 C.R. (5th) 308 at 320 (N.W.T.S.C.)Google Scholar
  5. R. v. Brenton [1999] N.W.T.J. No. 113Google Scholar
  6. R. v. Chaulk [2006] N.S.J. No 407Google Scholar
  7. R. v. Chaulk [2007] N.S.J. No. 301, 2007 N.S.C.A. 84Google Scholar
  8. R. v. Huppie [2008] A.J. No. 989Google Scholar
  9. R. v. Jensen [1991] B.C.J. No. 4060Google Scholar
  10. R. v. Kamipeli [1975] 2 N.Z.L.R. 610 at 616 (C.A.)Google Scholar
  11. R. v. Kataria [2005] B.C.J. No. 2963Google Scholar
  12. R. v. King [1962] 133 C.C.C. 1Google Scholar
  13. R. v. Penno [1990] 2 S.C.R. 865Google Scholar
  14. R. v. Talock [2003] 41 M.V.R. 269 (Sask. C.A.)Google Scholar
  15. R. v. Thompson [1993] O.J. No. 3249Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.York UniversityTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations