Skip to main content

Our Responsibility Towards Future Generations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Efficiency, Sustainability, and Justice to Future Generations

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 98))

Abstract

The future, for a long time, was a concept to which philosophers and jurists paid little attention. Barely any of the great thinkers of the past classed it as relevant to human action. Even Kant, who shows some signs of taking the problem of generational succession into consideration, bases his ethics on the presumption of the individual acting in the hic et nunc, for whom the future clearly remains a remote concern. The constant advancement of technology is now turning this conception upside down. The first to recognize the practical implications of this circumstance, and to suggest that the technological civilization called for a new ethics, was Hans Jonas. The following essay therefore begins with an appraisal of Hans Jonas, before proceeding to make a – prima facie – surprising comparison with Herbert Hart. Examination of the deficiencies of both perspectives opens up the avenue of transcendence which leads to a new orientation, at least an outline of which is put forward in conclusion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. von Savigny, pp. 42 f.

  2. 2.

    Quoted as in Kant, Universal History, p. 13.

  3. 3.

    Ibidem, p. 21.

  4. 4.

    Ibidem, p. 14: “It remains strange that the earlier generations appear to carry through their toilsome labor only for the sake of the later, to prepare for them a foundation on which the later generations could erect the higher edifice which was Nature’s goal, and yet that only the latest of the generations should have the good fortune to inhabit the building on which a long line of their ancestors had (unintentionally) labored without being permitted to partake of the fortune they had prepared. However puzzling this may be, it is necessary if one assumes that a species of animals should have reason, and, as a class of rational beings each of whom dies while the species is immortal, should develop their capacities to perfection.”

  5. 5.

    Cf. Kant, Conflict, p. 169.

  6. 6.

    Cf. F. G. Jünger, p. 232 (own trans.): “Man no longer masters the mechanical law which he himself has set in train; this law masters him”. Certainly the greater influence on Heidegger was the work of Ernst Jünger. See E. Jünger, Mobilmachung and Arbeiter.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Heidegger, ‘Technik’. For commentary, cf. Schirmacher; Seubold. Among recent publications: Luckner.

  8. 8.

    Cf. Heidegger, Language, pp. 102 f.: “‘Physics and responsibility ’ – that is a good thing, and important in today’s crisis. But it remains double-entry accounting behind which there is concealed a breach that can be cured neither by science nor by morality, if indeed it is curable at all.”

  9. 9.

    Of the recent literature, reference should at least be made to the comprehensive essay collection published by Bifulco and D’Aloia, to Birnbacher and Schicha, and to Schlothfeldt.

  10. 10.

    One of the first writings in which Jonas anticipates the main thesis of the book for which he became renowned is ‘Technology’, pp. 35 ff. (later in the anthology Jonas , Philosophical Essays, pp. 3 ff.). For an extensive discussion of Imperative, Müller is still useful. For a historical contextualization cf. Gethmann-Siefert, pp. 171 ff. Jonas ’ significance has not escaped one of the first juristic monographs on the topic: Saladin and Zenger, pp. 26 ff.

  11. 11.

    Cf. Weber. For a relevant discussion (in relation to Jonas ) cf. Nepi, pp. 95 ff.

  12. 12.

    Jonas, Imperative, p. 11.

  13. 13.

    Quoted as in Kant, Foundations, p. 47.

  14. 14.

    Jonas’ criticism of Kant seems to me to go no further, in essence, than the critisicm levelled at Kant’s ethics by Hegel , who referred to it as “empty formalism”. On this, see: Hegel, ‘Glauben’, p. 89; ‘Jacobi’, pp. 24 ff.; ‘Grundlinien’, Vol. VII, §§ 133–137, pp. 250 ff.; ‘Enzyklopädie’, Vol. VIII, §§ 53–54 (and supplementary notes), pp. 138 f.; ‘Vorlesungen’, Vol. XX, pp. 366 ff.; secondary literature: Knox, pp. 70 ff.; Ritter, pp. 281 ff.; Cesa, pp. 149 ff.; Ameriks, pp. 179 ff.

  15. 15.

    Cf. Jonas, ‘Technik’. On the complex relations between theory and practice in the Imperative, I refer to my essay ‘Diskrepanz’, pp. 239 ff.

  16. 16.

    Jonas, Imperative, p. 43.

  17. 17.

    Jonas, Imperative, pp. 43 f.

  18. 18.

    As the most challenging of Jonas ’ works proves very well. Cf. Phenomenon.

  19. 19.

    Jonas, Imperative, p. 81.

  20. 20.

    Jonas, Imperative, p. 131. And Jonas continues: “I mean strictly, just this: that here the plain being of a de facto existent immanently and evidently contains an ought for others, and would do so even if nature would not succour this ought with powerful instincts or assume its job alone.”

  21. 21.

    Starting from the objection argued by Apel , which is certainly one of the most thorough: ‘Verantwortung’, pp. 179 ff. And from among the recent publications, cf. Hirsch Hadorn, pp. 218 ff.

  22. 22.

    Cf. Jonas, ‘Grundlegung’, p. 140 (own trans.): “Yet ultimately my argument can do no more than rationally justify an option which it presents with its inherent persuasive force to the thinking individual. Unfortunately I have nothing better to offer. Perhaps a future metaphysics will be able to.”

  23. 23.

    In a radio interview, Jonas finds himself forced to admit this. His interviewer (Eike Gebhardt) had asked him: “Do you consider pure survival to be a value in itself, the greatest good so to speak, quite irrespective of what survives? Since you only argue ex negativo: might we call your position an ‘ethics of avoidance’?” And Jonas replied: “I would accept your expression ‘ethics of avoidance’; not as the definitive formula for an ethics, but in the sense of a temporary priority […]. I do not say that there can or ought to be a definitive ethics; but the situation has made it imperative that the avoidance of extreme dangers and extreme evil be prioritized, while the search for the best, the ideal or the exemplary human life, both for the individual and for society, steps into the background for the time being.” (Own trans., cf. ‘Naturwissenschaft’, pp. 208 ff.).

  24. 24.

    Cf. Hart, Concept, pp. 255 ff. In German-speaking legal philosophy, the argument of the minimum content of natural law has barely been discussed. (Cf. the brief presentation in the monograph by Eckmann, pp. 48 ff.). Among older publications, mention is made of Passerin d’Entrèves, pp. 312 ff., and Cattaneo, pp. 673 ff. Of the more recent publications, see: Rivaya, pp. 65 ff.; Orrego, pp. 287 ff. and Epstein, pp. 219 ff. In Italy two additional papers have been published on the theme: Ricciardi, pp. 221 ff. and Maestri, pp. 240 ff. Finally, mention is made of a work with a strong bearing on our problematique, Bifulco, pp. 61 ff.

  25. 25.

    Cf. Hart, ‘Positivism’, pp. 593 ff.

  26. 26.

    Cf. Kelsen, p. 56. Kelsen continues: “there is no human behaviour that would be excluded simply by virtue of its substance from becoming the content of a legal norm.”

  27. 27.

    See Hart, Concept, p. 187. Based on a few purely biological facts like the primary human needs (food, rest, etc.) Hart draws the self-evident conclusion: “it is the tacit assumption that the proper end of human activity is survival , and this rests on the simple contingent fact that most men most of the time wish to continue in existence. The actions which we speak of as those which are naturally good to do, are those which are required for survival ; […].”

  28. 28.

    Hart, Concept, p. 187. Here, Hart sets Hobbes and Hume against followers of the Aristotelian tradition because the latter did not confine themselves to survival as such but saw survival “as merely the lowest stratum in a much more complex and far more debatable concept of the human end or good for man”.

  29. 29.

    Hart, Concept, p. 188.

  30. 30.

    Hart, Concept, p. 188. See also p. 189: “In considering the simple truisms which we set forth here, and their connexion with law and morals, it is important to observe that in each case the facts mentioned afford a reason why, given survival as an aim, law and morals should include a specific content. The general form of the argument is simply that without such a content laws and morals could not forward the minimum purpose of survival which men have in associating with each other.”

  31. 31.

    Cf. Hobbes, p. 66.

  32. 32.

    Cf. Hume, p. 315.

  33. 33.

    One critique of Hart in this point is delivered by Barry , but it does not strike at Hart ’s central point, cf. Barry, p. 158.

  34. 34.

    Cf. Hume, p. 189.

  35. 35.

    Cf. Hume, pp. 210 ff.

  36. 36.

    Hart, Concept, p. 195.

  37. 37.

    von Jhering.

  38. 38.

    Hart, Concept, p. 195.

  39. 39.

    In this regard, cf. Bifulco, pp. 61 ff.

  40. 40.

    Cf. Hart, Concept, p. 195.

  41. 41.

    Cf. Hart, ‘Ascription’, pp. 145 ff.

  42. 42.

    Whether Hart is impermissibly deriving an “is” from an “ought” is a matter of controversy in the literature; see references in n. 24 above.

  43. 43.

    Quoted as in Nietzsche, p. 155.

  44. 44.

    Jonas, Imperative, p. 23. “It is moot whether, without restoring the category of the sacred, the category most thoroughly destroyed by the scientific enlightenment, we can have an ethics able to cope with the extreme powers which we possess today and constantly increase and are almost compelled to wield.”

  45. 45.

    Cf. Becchi, ‘Puzzle’, pp. 157 ff., and now in greater depth, Becchi, Principio.

Bibliography

  • Ameriks, Karl, ‘The Hegelian Critique of Kantian Morality’, in Bernard den Ouden (ed.), New Essays on Kant (New York, 1987), pp. 179 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apel, Karl-Otto, ‘Verantwortung heute – nur noch Prinzip der Bewahrung und Selbstbeschränkung oder immer noch der Befreiung und Verwirklichung von Humanität?’, in Karl-Otto Apel, Diskurs und Verantwortung. Das Problem des Übergangs zur postkonventionellen Moral (Frankfurt a.M., 1990; cited as: ‘Verantwortung’), pp. 179 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Brian, Theories of Justice (Berkeley, 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • Becchi, Paolo, ‘Gibt es eine Diskrepanz zwischen Theorie und Praxis des Prinzips Verantwortung?’, in Ralf Seidel and Meiken Endruweit (eds.), Prinzip Zukunft: Im Dialog mit Hans Jonas (Paderborn, 2007), pp. 239 ff. (cited as: ‘Diskrepanz’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Becchi, Paolo, ‘Das Puzzle der Menschenwürde’, in Paolo Becchi, Christoph B. Graber and Michele Luminati (eds.), Interdisziplinäre Wege in der juristischen Grundlagenforschung (Zurich, Basel and Geneva, 2007), pp. 157 ff. (cited as: ‘Puzzle’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Becchi, Paolo, Il principio dignità umana (Brescia, 2009; cited as: Principio)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bifulco, Raffaele and D’Aloia, Antonio, Un diritto per il futuro (Naples, 2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bifulco, Raffaele, Diritto e generazioni future. Problemi giuridici della responsabilità intergenerazionale (Milano, 2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbacher, Dieter and Schicha, Christian, ‘Vorsorge statt Nachhaltigkeit – ethische Grundlagen der Zukunftsverantwortung’, in Dieter Birnbacher and Gerd Brudermüller (eds.), Zukunftsverantwortung und Generationensolidarität, Schriften des Instituts für angewandte Ethik e.V., Vol. 3 (Würzburg, 2001), pp. 17 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cattaneo, Mario A., ‘Il diritto naturale nel pensiero di H.L.A. Hart’, in Rivista internazionale di filosofia del diritto, Vol. XLII (1965), pp. 673 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cesa, Claudio, ‘Tra Moralität e Sittlichkeit. Sul confronto di Hegel con la filosofia pratica di Kant’, in Valerio Verra (ed.), Hegel interprete di Kant (Naples, 1981), pp. 149 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eckmann, Horst, Rechtspositivismus und sprachanalytische Philosophie. Der Begriff des Rechts in der Rechtstheorie H. L. A. Harts (Berlin, 1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, Richard A., ‘The not so minimum content of natural law’, in Oxford Journal of legal studies, Vol. 2 (2005), pp. 219 ff.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gethmann-Siefert, Annemarie, ‘Ethos und metaphysische Erbe. Zu den Grundlagen von Hans Jonas’ Ethik der Verantwortung’, in Herbert Schädelbach and Geert Keil (eds.), Philosophie der Gegenwart. Gegenwart der Philosophie (Hamburg, 1993), pp. 171 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L.A., ‘The Ascription of Responsibility and Rights’, in Antony Flew (ed.), Essay on Logic and Language (Oxford, 1951), pp. 145 ff. (cited as: ‘Ascription’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L.A., ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’, in Harvard Law Review, Vol. 71 (1958), pp. 593 ff. (cited as: ‘Positivism’)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L.A., The Concept of Law (London, 1961; cited as: Concept)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F., ‘Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse’, in Eva Moldenhauer and Kurt Markus Michel (eds.), Werke in zwanzig Bänden, Vol. VII (Frankfurt a.M., 1969–1971), pp. 250 ff. (cited as: ‘Grundlinien’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F., ‘Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830)’, in Werke in zwanzig Bänden, Vol. VIII (Frankfurt a.M., 1969–1971), pp. 138 f. (cited as: ‘Enzyklopädie’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F., ‘Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie III’, in Werke in zwanzig Bänden, Vol. XX (Frankfurt a.M., 1969–1971), pp. 366 ff. (cited as: ‘Vorlesungen’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F., ‘Glauben und Wissen, oder die Reflexionsphilosophie der Subjektivität in der Vollständigkeit ihrer Formen, als Kantische, Jacobische, Fichtesche Philosophie’, in Hans Brockard and Hartmut Buchner (eds.), Jenaer Kritische Schriften (III) (Hamburg, 1986), p. 89 (cited as: ‘Glauben’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F., ‘Jacobi-Rezension’, in id., Berliner Schriften (1818–1831), ed. Walter Jaeschke (Hamburg, 1997), pp. 8 ff. (cited as: ‘Jacobi’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin, ‘Die Frage nach der Technik’ (1950), in id., Vorträge und Aufsätze (Pfullingen, 1962), pp. 37 ff.; published in English as Martin Heidegger, The question concerning technology, and other essays, trans. and with an introduction by William Lovitt (New York, 1977; cited as: ‘Technik’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin, On the Way to Language (= Unterwegs zur Sprache, 1959), trans. Peter D. Hertz (New York, 1971; cited as: Language)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch Hadorn, Gertrude, ‘Verantwortungsbegriff und Kategorischer Imperativ der Zukunftsethik’, in Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, Vol. 54 (2000), pp. 218 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan (1651; 5th edn., London, 1885)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739/40), Vol. II, Passions – Morals (London, 1817)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans, The Phenomenon of Life. Towards a Philosophical Biology (New York, 1966; cited as: Phenomenon)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans, ‘Technology and Responsibility. Reflections on the New Tasks of Ethics’, in Social Research, Vol. 40 (1973), pp. 35 ff. (cited as: ‘Technology’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans, Philosophical Essays. From Ancient Creed to Technological Man (Chicago, 1974; cited as: Philosophical Essays)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago and London, 1984, paperback edition 1985; cited as: Imperative)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans, Technik, Medizin und Ethik. Praxis des Prinzips Verantwortung (Frankfurt a.M., 1985; cited as: Technik)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans, ‘Zur ontologischen Grundlegung einer Zukunftsethik’ (1985), now in id. (ed.), Philosophische Untersuchungen und metaphysische Vermutungen (Frankfurt a.M. and Leipzig, 1992), pp. 128 ff. (cited as: ‘Grundlegung’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, Hans, ‘Naturwissenschaft versus Natur-Verantwortung’, in Dietrich Böhler (ed.), Ethik für die Zukunft. Im Diskurs mit Hans Jonas (Munich, 1994), pp. 197 ff. (cited as: ‘Naturwissenschaft’)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jünger, Ernst, Die totale Mobilmachung (Berlin, 1931; cited as: Mobilmachung)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jünger, Ernst, Der Arbeiter. Herrschaft und Gestalt (Hamburg, 1932; cited as: Arbeiter)

    Google Scholar 

  • Jünger, Friedrich G., Die Perfektion der Technik (1939) (2nd edn., Frankfurt a.M., 1949)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (= Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, 1785), trans. Lewis W. Beck (Indianapolis, 1959; cited as: Foundations)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel, Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of View (= Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher Absicht, 1784), trans. Lewis W. Beck (Indianapolis, 1963; cited as: Universal History)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel, The Conflict of the Faculties (= Der Streit der Fakultäten, 1798) trans. and introduction by Mary J. Gregor, paperback edition (New York, 1979; cited as: Conflict)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans, Reine Rechtslehre (Vienna, 1960), quoted here from Hans Kelsen, Introduction to the pure theory of law: a translation of the first edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or Pure theory of law, trans. Bonnie Litschewski Paulson and Stanley L. Paulson (Oxford, 1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Knox, Thomas M., ‘Hegel’s Attitude to Kant’s Ethics’, in Kant-Studien, Vol. 49 (1957–58), pp. 70 ff.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luckner, Andreas, Heidegger und das Denken der Technik (Bielefeld, 2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Maestri, Enrico, Giudizi di esistenza. Deliberare sulla vita umana nella riflessione bioetica contemporanea (Napoli, 2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Wolfgang E., Der Begriff der Verantwortung bei Hans Jonas (Frankfurt a.M., 1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nepi, Paolo, La responsabilità ontologica. L’uomo e il mondo nell’etica di Hans Jonas (Rome, 2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich, On the Genealogy of Morals (1887), ed. and trans. Walter A. Kaufmann (New York, 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • Orrego, Cristóbal, ‘H. L. A. Hart’s Understanding of Classical Natural Law Theory’, in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 2 (2004), pp. 287 ff.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Passerin d’Entrèves, Alessandro, ‘“Un noyau de bon sens”. À propos de la théorie du droit naturel chez H. Hart’, in Revue internationale de philosophie, Vol. 17 (1963), n. 65, fasc. 3

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricciardi, Mario, Diritto e natura. H. L. A. Hart e la filosofia di Oxford (Pisa, 2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ritter, Joachim, ‘Moralität und Sittlichkeit. Zu Hegels Auseinandersetzung mit der kantischen Ethik’, in Metaphysik und Politik. Studien zu Aristoteles und Hegel (Frankfurt a.M., 1969), pp. 281 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivaya, Benjamin, ‘On theories of the minimum content of natural law – constructions or reconstruction’, in Rechtstheorie, Vol. 32 (2001), pp. 65 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saladin, Peter and Zenger, Christoph A., Rechte künftiger Generationen (Basel and Frankfurt a.M., 1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schirmacher, Wolfgang, Technik und Gelassenheit. Zeitkritik nach Heidegger (Freiburg im Breisgau and Munich, 1983)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlothfeldt, Stephan, ‘Wer trägt die Verantwortung für zukünftige Generationen’, in Carmen Kaminsky and Oliver Hallich (eds.), Verantwortung für die Zukunft: zum 60. Geburtstag von Dieter Birnbacher, Ethik in der Praxis, Vol. 22 (Berlin, 2006), pp. 37 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seubold, Günter, Heideggers Analyse der neuzeitlichen Technik (Freiburg im Breisgau and Munich, 1986)

    Google Scholar 

  • von Jhering, Rudolf, Der Zweck im Recht (1877–1883), Volumes 1 and 2. Vol. 1 translated into English as Law as a Means to an End, trans. Isaac Husik (Boston, 1913)

    Google Scholar 

  • von Savigny, Friedrich C., Of the Vocation of our Age for Legislation and Jurisprudence (= Vom Beruf unserer Zeit für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft, 1814), trans. Abraham Hayward (2nd edn., London, 1831, reprinted 2002 by The Lawbook Exchange Ltd.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max, The Vocation Lectures. Science as a Vocation, Politics as a Vocation (= Wissenschaft als Beruf, 1917/1919. Politik als Beruf, 1919), ed. and with an introduction by David Owen and Tracy B. Strong, trans. Rodney Livingstone (Indianapolis, 2004)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paolo Becchi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Becchi, P. (2012). Our Responsibility Towards Future Generations. In: Mathis, K. (eds) Efficiency, Sustainability, and Justice to Future Generations. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 98. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1869-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics