Skip to main content

Personal Epistemology and Philosophical Epistemology: The View of a Philosopher

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Links Between Beliefs and Cognitive Flexibility

Abstract

Recently, it has been suggested that there is a need for a conceptual clarification of the relation between personal epistemology (PE) and philosophical epistemology. I attempt to do this in this chapter. First, I clarify the task of traditional epistemology as understood by philosophers and point out how it is different from epistemology as understood by PE researchers: epistemology is not postmodernist; it has a normative goal, which is different from empirical research; subfields of epistemology are briefly mentioned and implications for PE research suggested. Second, I point out the existence of several conceptual pitfalls that should be avoided by individuals working in this area: epistemic versus epistemological, 1st person versus 3rd person perspectives, and an important ambiguity in the concept of cognition. Third, the concept of cognitive flexibility in relation to epistemology needs to be carefully discussed, especially in relation to the issue of domain specificity and domain generality. This is discussed in the context of an epistemology of pragmatism. Finally, I mention the recent revolution produced by naturalistic epistemology and the implications of this challenge for understanding the relation between PE and traditional epistemology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I can’t resist mentioning that in all of the PE articles I have read, there is a singular scarcity of references to standard textbooks in epistemology. Needless to say, I find this consistent absence puzzling and disquieting.

  2. 2.

    Part of the confusion about a priori knowledge is due to the several ways in which Kant uses that term. Among most epistemologists, however, the preferred view is to interpret “a priori” as meaning independent of experience of and not temporally prior to experience (innate).

  3. 3.

    A related question of the following: assuming there is a distinction between analytic propositions and synthetic propositions, with analytic propositions being a priori, do students grasp the difference between analytic and synthetic propositions and if so, how does this comprehension develop over time? Again, I have pretty much looked in vain for studies concerning this question.

References

  • Alston, W. (2005). Beyond “justification”: Dimensions of epistemic evaluation. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1993). The structure of justification. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxter Magolda, M. B. (2004). Evolution of a constructivist conceptualization of epistemological reflection. Educational Psychologist, 39, 31–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1991). Knowledge and social imagery (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bochenski, J. M. (1965). The methods of contemporary thought (P. Caws, Trans.). Dordrecht, the Netherlands: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buehl, M. M., & Alexander, P. A. (2001). Beliefs about academic knowledge. Educational Psychology Review, 13, 385–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burbules, N. C. (1995). Postmodern doubt and philosophy of education. www.ed.uiec.edu/EPS/PES-Yearbook/95-docs/burbules.html.

  • Dewey, J. (1910). The influence of Darwin on philosophy and other essays. New York: P. Smith.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1929). The quest for certainty. New York: Putnam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. New York: H. Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1949). Knowing and the known. Boston: Beacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1994). The origins of analytic philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R., & Hamilton, R. J. (Eds.). (1992). Philosophy of science, cognitive psychology and educational theory and practice. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzgerald, J., & Cunningham, J. W. (2002). Mapping basic issues for identifying epistemological outlooks. In B. Hofer & P. Pintrich (Eds.), Personal epistemology: The psychology of beliefs about knowledge and knowing (pp. 209–228). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flavell, J. H. (1988). The development of children’s knowledge about the mind: From cognitive connections to mental representations. In J. W. Astington, P. L. Harris, & D. R. Olson (Eds.), Developing theories of mind (pp. 244–270). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofer, B. (2002). Personal epistemology as a psychological and educational construct: An introduction. In B. K. Hofer & P. R. Pintrich (Eds.), Personal epistemology: The psychology of beliefs about knowledge and knowing (pp. 3–14). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofer, B. (2006). Beliefs about knowledge and knowing: Integrating domain specificity and domain generality: A response to Muis, Bendexin, & Haerle. Educational Psychology Review, 18, 67–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofer, B. K., & Pintrich, P. R. (1987). The development of epistemological theories: Beliefs about knowledge and knowing and their relation to learning. Review of Educational Research, 67, 88–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofer, B. K., & Pintrich, P. R. (Eds.). (2002). Personal epistemology: The psychology of beliefs about knowledge and knowing. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, P., & Kitchener, K. S. (1994). Developing reflective judgment: Understanding and promoting intellectual growth and critical thinking in adolescents and adults. San Francisco: Jossey Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitchener, R. F. (1986). Piaget’s theory of knowledge: Genetic epistemology and scientific reason. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitchener, R. F. (1991). Do children think philosophically? Thoughts after Piaget. Metaphilosophy, 21, 416–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitchener, R. F. (Ed.). (2002). Folk epistemology. New Ideas in Psychology, 20, 89–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitchener, R. F. (2008). On the concept(s) of the social in Piaget. In U. Müller, J. Carpendale, & L. Smith (Eds.), Cambridge companion to Piaget (pp. 110–131). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitchener, R. F. (forthcoming). Developmental epistemology: Cognitive-developmental psychology and naturalistic epistemology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1992). The naturalists return. Philosophical Review, 101, 53–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1981). Essays on moral development (Vol. I: The philosophy of moral development). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolakowski, L. (1968). The alienation of reason: A history of positivist thought (N. Buterman, Trans.). New York: Doubleday. (Original work published 1966)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (Ed.). (1994). Naturalizing epistemology (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (Ed.). (2001). Epistemology: Internalism and externalism. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kruglanski, A. (1989). Lay epistemics and human knowledge: Cognitive and motivational bases. New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1968). Theories of scientific method from Plato to Mach: A bibliographic review. History of Science, 7, 1–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Losee, J. (2001). A historical introduction to the philosophy of science (4th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, J. F. (1984). The postmodern condition: A report on knowledge (G. Bennington & B. Massumi, Trans.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maffie, J. (1990). Recent work on naturalized epistemology. American Philosophical Quarterly, 27, 281–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1994). Science teaching: The role of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, W. S. (2002). Understanding learning in a postmodern world: Reconsidering the Perry scheme of ethical and intellectual development. In B. K. Hofer & P. R. Pintrich (Eds.), Personal epistemology: The psychology of beliefs about knowledge and knowing (pp. 17–36). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muis, K. R., Bendixen, L. D., & Haerle, F. C. (2006). Domain-generality and domain-specificity in personal epistemology research: Philosophical and empirical reflections on the development of a theoretical framework. Educational Psychology Review, 18, 3–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Passmore, J. (1961). Philosophical reasoning. New York: Scribner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1971). Biology and knowledge: An essay on the relations between organic regulations and cognitive processes (B. Walsh, Trans.) Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1967)

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1985). The equilibration of cognitive structures: The central problem of intellectual development (T. Brown & K. J. Thampy, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1975)

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J., Apostel, L., Mays, W., & Morf, A. (1957). Les liaisons analytiques et synthétiques dans les comportements du sujet. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1961a). Meno (W. K. C. Guthrie, Trans.). In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), The collected dialogues of Plato (pp. 353–384). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1961b). Theaetetus (F. M. Cornford, Trans.). In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), The collected dialogues of Plato (pp. 845–919). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, A. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, F. F. (Ed.). (1994). Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, L. (1993). Necessary knowledge: Piagetian perspectives on constructivism. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southerland, S. A., Sinatra, G. M., & Matthews, M. R. (2001). Belief, knowledge, and science education. Educational Psychology Review, 13, 325–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2001). Epistemic justification. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Karen Strohm Kitchener for reading and commenting on an earlier version of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard F. Kitchener .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kitchener, R.F. (2011). Personal Epistemology and Philosophical Epistemology: The View of a Philosopher. In: Elen, J., Stahl, E., Bromme, R., Clarebout, G. (eds) Links Between Beliefs and Cognitive Flexibility. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1793-0_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics