Skip to main content

Thomas Kuhn and Interdisciplinary Conversation: Why Historians and Philosophers of Science Stopped Talking to One Another

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Integrating History and Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 263))

Abstract

This paper looks back to Thomas S. Kuhn’s seminal work of 1962, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, as a landmark in the relations between history and philosophy of science. I propose that Kuhn’s book, though read both by historians and by philosophers, contributed to the process by which they have developed largely separate concerns in recent decades. Kuhn was a committed participant in interdisciplinary discourse, and yet his book was read in fundamentally different ways in the two disciplinary communities. To understand how this happened, I propose that we need to modify Kuhn’s own categories of historical analysis to recognize the bearing on disciplinary communities of factors that he discounted as “external.” I argue that philosophers and historians approached Kuhn’s work with preoccupations shaped by the cultural and political context of Cold War debates about science, though that context yielded very different orientations in the two communities.

Paradigm was a perfectly good word until I messed it up

– Thomas S. Kuhn

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Fuller (2000) and Zammito (2004) together provide the nearest thing available to an intellectual history of Kuhn’s work and its influence on science studies. Fuller also provides some valuable biographical information, and the autobiographical comments in “A Discussion with Thomas S, Kuhn,” in Kuhn (2000, 255–323), are also valuable. An illuminating article, Andresen (1999), indicates the possibility for more work along these lines. Philosophical studies of Kuhn include: Bird (2000) and Hoyningen-Huene (1993).

  2. 2.

    On the “marriage” and prospects for divorce, see Zammito (2004, 95–96).

  3. 3.

    The importance of the Cold War context in Kuhn’s work is emphasized by Fuller (2000, esp. 1–37). Although I have learned a lot from Fuller, readers will be able to discern that I do not share his overall interpretation of Kuhn, which portrays him as an ideological foot soldier in a Cold-War campaign to shield science from critical examination. Instead, I see aspects of the ideological context of the times as having shaped the readings of Kuhn’s work in sometimes contradictory and paradoxical ways, and often against his own inclination. The various contemporary readings of Kuhn’s Structure reflect the multiple interests of its readers, and do not require us to suppose, as Fuller does, that Kuhn’s work was largely vacuous and unworthy of serious attention. Nor do I share Fuller’s view that Kuhn’s influence constituted a malign force shaping the whole field of science studies. As I shall indicate, I see Kuhn as having little positive influence on philosophers and almost none (directly) on historians. His most significant influence within science studies was mediated by sociologists, whose reading of his work he specifically repudiated.

  4. 4.

    On Newton, see Stewart (1996), Snobelen (2001). On Darwin, see Young (1985), Moore (1979). On Einstein, see Warwick (1992, 1993).

  5. 5.

    The intellectual historian Peter Novick has written: “one cannot reduce Popper’s philosophy to his struggle against Marxism, but that concern permeated all his work”—including, I would suggest, his response to Kuhn (Novick 1998, 298). See also Hacohen (2000, 530–34).

  6. 6.

    On the previous history of arguments over relativism, see Herbert (2001), Smith (2006, 18–45), Novick (1988, 133–67, 281–319).

  7. 7.

    Merton, “Science and the Social Order” (1938), quoted in Novick (1988, 289). On Merton’s interpretation of Mannheim, see Kaiser (1998).

  8. 8.

    Popper (1945, 2:187–211). On Popper’s work in this connection, see Hacohen (2000, 512–13), Novick (1988, 298–99), Anderson (1992, 60–65, 71–72).

  9. 9.

    On Bernal, see Brown (2005).

  10. 10.

    Polanyi had criticized Bernal and other Marxists since the late 1930s for subordinating science to social ends and denying its autonomy as a search for truth. See Scott and Moleski (2005, 174–75). For Polanyi’s influence on Kuhn, see Fuller (2000, 139–49).

  11. 11.

    Kuhn’s most important statement on the topic after Structure was “Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability” (1983), in Kuhn (2000, 33–57). See also Zammito (2004, 52–89), Hoyningen-Huene (1993, 206–22). Zammito notes that Kuhn’s acceptance that the problem of incommensurability was basically a linguistic issue, as asserted by such philosophers as Dudley Shapere and Israel Sheffler, was ultimately self-frustrating. It is hard to avoid the reflection that the debate that resulted was an instance of sustained mutual incomprehension, if not of ultimate linguistic incommensurability, between Kuhn and his philosophical interlocutors. His continued struggles to resolve the issues at stake suggest, however, that Kuhn was reluctant to acknowledge this.

  12. 12.

    See especially Kuhn’s lecture at Harvard University in 1991: “The Trouble with Historical Philosophy of Science,” in Kuhn (2000, 105–20).

  13. 13.

    On the London conference and its impact, see Werskey (1988, 138–49), Mayer (2004).

  14. 14.

    Robert K. Merton, “The Normative Structure of Science” (1942), in Merton (1973, 267–78). See also Mendelsohn (1989), Hollinger (1983). Peter Novick has noted that Merton’s original explanation of the coincidence between scientific norms and the values of a democratic society specifically criticized only Nazi Germany. When the exposition was revised in 1949, criticisms of the Soviet Union were added. See Novick (1988, 296–97 fn. 28).

  15. 15.

    Kuhn (1962/1970, 174–210). See also Kuhn (2000, 286–87), where Kuhn records that he saw his own work as “pretty straight internalist” and was surprised when Alexandre Koyré congratulated him for having brought together internalist and externalist approaches.

  16. 16.

    On Conant, see Fuller (2000, 150–226), Kuhn (2000, 275–76, 282–89). See also Fuller (2000, 60–70 (on Koyré), 392–97 (on Meyerson)), Chimisso (2001), Dennis (2003), Porter (1986).

  17. 17.

    Introducing a new edition of his text in 1990, Gillispie acknowledged that the discipline of history of science had shifted in the intervening years to embrace a more externalist outlook, a shift that he ascribed to the leftist cultural movements of the 1960s and 1970s. See Gillispie (1990, xiv–xv, xvi–xvii, xx–xxi).

  18. 18.

    Hollinger (1995). See also Dennis (2003), who points out that Henry Guerlac at Cornell represented an alternative approach, open to consideration of external influences on scientific development and anticipating some of what followed after Kuhn.

  19. 19.

    Porter (1986).

  20. 20.

    On Cavell, see Kuhn (2000, 297).

  21. 21.

    Barnes (1982, 1985), Bloor (1983, 1991).

  22. 22.

    Kuhn (1962/1970, 18–19). See also Barnes (1982, 120–26).

  23. 23.

    Shapin (1995, esp. 294–98), Zammito (2004, 124–26).

  24. 24.

    Collins’s case-studies of scientific controversies were later collected in Collins (1985). See also Shapin and Schaffer (1985), Rudwick (1985), and Kuhn (1962/1970, quote on 94).

  25. 25.

    Bloor (1991, 3–23, 157–61, 175–79).

  26. 26.

    Barnes and Bloor (1982, 47).

  27. 27.

    Kuhn (2000, 315–16).

  28. 28.

    Bloor (1991, 7, 175–79).

  29. 29.

    Zammito (2004, 137–50).

  30. 30.

    Kuhn (2000, 255–323).

References

  • Andresen, Jensine. 1999. Crisis and Kuhn. Isis 90: S43–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Perry. 1992. English Questions. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Barry. 1982. T. S. Kuhn and Social Science. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Barry. 1985. “Thomas Kuhn.” In The Return of Grand Theory in the Human Sciences, edited by Quentin Skinner, 83–100. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Barry, and David Bloor. 1982. “Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge.” In Rationality and Relativism, edited by Martin Hollis and Steven Lukes, 21–47. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, Alexander. 2000. Thomas Kuhn. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David. 1983. Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David. 1991. Knowledge and Social Imagery. 2nd edition. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Andrew. 2005. J. D. Bernal: The Sage of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chimisso, Cristina. 2001. “Hélène Metzger: The History of Science Between the Study of Mentalities and Total History.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 32: 203–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 1985. Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. Beverly Hills and London: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennis, Michael Aaron. 2003. “Historiography of Science: An American Perspective.” In Companion to Science in the Twentieth Century, edited by John Krige and Dominique Pestre, 1–26. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael. 1998. “On the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge and Its Philosophical Agenda.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29: 239–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Steve. 2000. Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Times. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillispie, Charles C. 1957. “[Review of Joseph Needham, Science and Civilization in China, vol. 2].” American Scientist 45: 169–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillispie, Charles C. 1990. The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas. 2nd edition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacohen, Malachi Hai. 2000. Karl Popper: The Formative Years, 1902–1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbert, Christopher. 2001. Victorian Relativity: Radical Thought and Scientific Discovery. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollinger, David A. 1983. “The Defense of Democracy and Robert K. Merton’s Formulation of the Scientific Ethos.” Knowledge and Society: Studies in the Sociology of Culture Past and Present 4: 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollinger, David A. 1990. “Free Enterprise and Free Inquiry: The Emergence of Laissez-Faire Communitarianism in the Ideology of Science in the United States.” New Literary History 21: 897–919.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollinger, David A. 1995. “Science as a Weapon in Kulturkämpfe in the United States During and After World War II.” Isis 86: 440–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, Paul. 1993. Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadvany, John. 2001. Imre Lakatos and the Guises of Reason. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, David. 1998. “A Mannheim for all Seasons: Bloor, Merton, and the Roots of the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.” Science in Context 11: 51–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, M.D. 1980. “Reason, Tradition, and the Progressiveness of Science.” In Paradigms and Revolutions: Appraisals and Applications of Thomas Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science, edited by Gary Gutting, 97–116. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962/1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd edition. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 2000. The Road Since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, edited by James Conant and John Haugeland. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, Imre 1970. “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, edited by Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, 91–196. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, Anna K. 2000. “Setting up a Discipline: Conflicting Agendas of the Cambridge History of Science Committee, 1936 –1950.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 31A:665–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, Anna K. 2004. “Setting up a Discipline II: British History of Science and ‘the End of Ideology’, 1931–1948.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35A: 41–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendelsohn, Everett. 1989. “Robert K. Merton: The Celebration and Defense of Science.” Science in Context 3: 269–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, Robert K. 1973. “Science and the Social Order.” In The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, edited by Norman W. Storer. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, James R. 1979. The Post-Darwinian Controversies: A Study of the Protestant Struggle to Come to Terms with Darwin in Great Britain and America, 1870–1900. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Novick, Peter. 1988. That Noble Dream: The “Objectivity Question” and the American Historical Profession. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Orwell, George. 1970. The Collected Essays, Journalism and Letters of George Orwell, edited by Sonia Orwell and Ian Angus. 4 vols. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl R. 1945. The Open Society and Its Enemies. 2 vols. London: George Routledge and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl R. 1970. “Normal Science and Its Dangers.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, edited by Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, 51–58. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, Roy. 1986. “The Scientific Revolution: A Spoke in the Wheel?” In Revolution in History, edited by Roy Porter and Mikuláš Teich, 290–316. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudwick, Martin. 1985. The Great Devonian Controversy: The Shaping of Scientific Knowledge Among Gentlemanly Specialists. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, William Taussig, and Martin X. Moleski, S.J. 2005. Michael Polanyi: Scientist and Philosopher. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 1992. “Discipline and Bounding: The History and Sociology of Science as Seen Through the Externalism-Internalism Debate.” History of Science 30: 333–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 1995. “Here and Everywhere: Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.” Annual Review of Sociology 21: 289–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven, and Simon Schaffer. 1985. Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Barbara Herrnstein. 2006. Scandalous Knowledge: Science, Truth and the Human. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snobelen, S.D. 2001. “‘God of Gods, and Lord of Lords’: The Theology of Isaac Newton’s General Scholium to the Principia.” Osiris 16: 169–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, Larry. 1996. “Seeing Through the Scholium: Religion and Reading Newton in the Eighteenth Century.” History of Science 34: 123–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, Frederick, ed. 1977. The Structure of Scientific Theories. 2nd edition. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warwick, Andrew C. 1992 and 1993. “Cambridge Mathematics and Cavendish Physics: Cunningham, Campbell and Einstein’s Relativity 1905–1911.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 23: 625–56; 24: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werskey, Gary. 1988. The Visible College: A Collective Biography of British Scientists and Socialists of the 1930s. 2nd edition. London: Free Association Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Robert M. 1985. “Darwin’s Metaphor: Does Nature Select?” In Darwin’s Metaphor: Nature’s Place in Victorian Culture, 79–125. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, John H. 2004. A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Post-Positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan Golinski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Golinski, J. (2011). Thomas Kuhn and Interdisciplinary Conversation: Why Historians and Philosophers of Science Stopped Talking to One Another. In: Mauskopf, S., Schmaltz, T. (eds) Integrating History and Philosophy of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 263. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1745-9_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics