Skip to main content

Fabri and Conservation of Rectilinear Motion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Honoré Fabri and the Concept of Impetus: A Bridge between Paradigms

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 288))

  • 425 Accesses

Abstract

This is a mainly historiographic chapter, which introduces Part III – entitled “Violent Motion”. This chapter describes the common (erroneous) agreement among historians (especially since Annelise Maier and Alexandre Koyré), that Jesuits in general – and Fabri in particular – adamantly rejected inertia, or more exactly, Conservation of Rectilinear Motion, i.e. the assertion that an object once moved in a certain direction, and henceforth affected by no other factor, will continue ad infinitum in its motion along that very direction with uniform velocity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I have discussed this aspect (in less detail than here) in Elazar 2008.

  2. 2.

    In theorem 62 of the first book of Fabri’s Tractatus physicus de motu locali (1646) he explains that a force applied on a leaden ball will move it more slowly than the same force applied to a much lighter ivory ball (with the same diameter) because of some “laziness of matter” (inertia materiae) which inhibits motion: “sit globus plumbeus 12 librarum, sit eburneus eiusdem diametri 2 librarum, v.g. haud dubie eadem potentia producet intensiorem impetum in eburneo, ut patet experientia, & ratio constat ex dictis; quasi vero sit aliqua materiae inertia, quae motum respuat” (Fabri 1646, lib. 1, th. 62, p. 40). See also Section 11.2 above.

  3. 3.

    Maier 1951, pp. 312–313. This is how Fabri describes some of Descartes’ views, which he himself renounces (a passage quoted by Maier): “Docet… Deum omnium motuum solam causam esse; nihil reale et positivum in corpore moto reperiri, quod quiescenti non insit; legibus naturae adversari ut quiescat id quod semel movetur aut moveatur quod semel quiescit; omnem motum ex natura sua rectum esse” (Fabri 1674, p. 26; see also “Honoré Fabri: A Short Biography” above). Fabri’s exact motives in formulating such an anxious attempt to distance himself from Descartes’ philosophy are still not entirely clear – further research is required concerning this issue; it is highly probable though that it is connected to Descartes’ 1663 condemnation, under Jesuit pressure and with the possible involvement of Fabri’s himself (see Section 19.4 below).

  4. 4.

    Clavelin 1974, p. 102, n. 116.

  5. 5.

    Drake 1975, p. 33, n. 3.

  6. 6.

    Galluzzi 2001, p. 267, n. 93.

  7. 7.

    Baldini 2004, p. 106. In his article Baldini shows that the prominent Jesuit Gabriel Vazquez was “an important and even surprising exception” among the Jesuits (ibid., p. 107), adopting Buridan’s view of the impetus as a non “self-consuming” property and yet rejecting Buridan’s claim that motion without resistance (e.g. in void) is by definition impossible (ibid., p. 135). It seems worth checking for a possible influence of Vasquez on Fabri, as well as searching for some other contemporary Jesuits (even less explored by modern historians than Fabri and Vasquez) who might also be revealed as “exceptions”.

  8. 8.

    See Blum 1999, p. 235, as well as Note 3 above.

References

  • Baldini, Ugo. 2004. Ontology and Mechanics in Jesuit Scholasticism: The Case of Gabriel Vasquez. In Scientiae et Artes: Die Vermittlung alten und neuen wissens in Literatur, Kunst und Music, ed. Barbara Mahlmann-Bauer, 99–142. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz in Kommission.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertoloni Meli, Domenico. 2000. Inertia. In Encyclopedia of the Scientific Revolution: From Copernicus to Newton, ed. W. Applebaum, 326–328. New York, NY: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blum, Paul Richard. 1999. Aristotelianism more geometrico: Honoré Fabri. In Philosophy in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries: Conversations with Aristotle, ed. Constance Blackwell, 234–247. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, Alfred. 1965. L’aristotélisme d’Honoré Fabri (1607–1688). Revue des science religieuses 39:305–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clavelin, Maurice. 1974. The Natural Philosophy of Galileo: Essay on the Origins and Formation of Classical Mechanics (trans: Pomerans, A.J.). Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Des Chene, Dennis. 1996. Physiologia: Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drake, Stillman. 1974. Impetus Theory and Quanta of Speed Before and After Galileo. Physis 16:47–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drake, Stillman. 1975. Impetus Theory Reappraised. Journal of the History of Ideas 36(1):27–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elazar, Michael. 2008. Honoré Fabri and the Trojan Horse of Inertia. Science in Context 21(1):1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fabri, Honoré. 1646. Tractatus physicus de motu locali, in quo effectus omnes, qui ad impetum, motum naturalem, violentum, & mixtum pertinent, explicantur, & ex principiis physicis demonstrantur; auctore Petro Mousnerio Doctore Medico; cuncta excerpta ex praelectionibus R. P. Honorati Fabry, Societatis Iesu. Lyon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabri, Honoré. 1674. Honorati Fabri societatis Iesu Ad P. Ignatium Gastonem Pardesium, eiusdem societatis Iesu, epistolae tres de sua hypothesi philosophica. Mainz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbey, Alan. 1980. Force and Inertia in the Seventeenth Century: Descartes and Newton. In Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics and Physics, ed. Stephen Gaukroger, 230–320. Sussex: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galluzzi, Paolo. 2001. Gassendi and laffaire Galilée of the Laws of Motion. In Galileo in context, ed. Jürgen Renn, 239–275. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graneau, Peter, and Neal Graneau. 2006. In the Grip of the Distant Universe: The Science of Inertia. Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Annaliese. 1951. Zwei Grundprobleme der scholastischen Naturphilosophie: Das Problem der intensiven Grösse; Die Impetustheorie. Rome: Edizioni di storia e letteratura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Annaliese. 1982. On the Threshold of Exact Science: Selected Writings of Anneliese Maier on Late Medieval Natural Philosophy (ed. and trans: Sargent, S.D.). Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, Isaac. 1999. The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (trans: Cohen, B. and Whitman, A.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redondi, Pietro. 1987. Galileo Heretic. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Elazar .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Elazar, M. (2011). Fabri and Conservation of Rectilinear Motion. In: Honoré Fabri and the Concept of Impetus: A Bridge between Paradigms. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 288. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1605-6_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics