Skip to main content

Legal Argumentation Theory and the Concept of Law

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 8))

Abstract

There has been wide recognition over the last three decades that argumentation plays a pivotal role in shaping the law, since practically any stage of what is ordinarily considered the legal domain involves recourse to reasoning.1 Legal scientists put forward interpretive statements: they propose what they see as reasonable interpretations of laws and defend these interpretations with arguments. Both of these tasks require reasoning. Lawyers, when they bring cases to court, must do more or less the same (even if the aims here are more specific and concrete): they interpret general norms and precedents, qualify concrete cases and offer reasons in support of their conclusions. Judges decide cases, an activity which makes it necessary to find and sometimes reconstruct the rule of law, interpret rules and apply them to concrete circumstances, weigh principles, settle conflicts between norms encased in the same legal order, follow precedents, ascertain and qualify facts, determine the most reasonable solution to the case at hand, and put forward justifications for their decisions. All such operations are argumentative. And lastly, in a constitutional democratic state the legislators, too, will tend to offer reasons backing their deliberations, so as to make them more easily acceptable to the people they govern. In doing so even the legislators accept to take part in the game of argumentation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Aarnio, A. (1987). The Rational as Reasonable. A Treatise on Legal Justification. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aarnio, A., Alexy R., & Peczenik A. (1981). The Foundation of Legal Reasoning. Rechtstheorie, 21, 133–158; 259-273; 423-448.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. (1989a). A Theory of Legal Argumentation (1978). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. (1989b). On necessary relations between law and morality. Ratio Juris, 167–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. (1996). Interpretazione giuridica. In Enciclopedia delle scienze sociali, vol. V (pp. 64–71). Roma: Istituto dell’ enciclopedia italiana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. (2000). On the thesis of a necessary connection between law and morality: Bulygin’s Critique. Ratio Juris, 138–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. (2002a). A Theory of Constitutional Rights (1986). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. (2002b). The Argument from injustice (1992). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. & Dreier, R. (1991). Statutory interpretation in the Federal Republic of Germany. In N. MacCormick & R. S. Summers (Eds.), Interpreting Statutes (pp. 73–121). Aldershot: Dartmouth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1978). Taking Rights Seriously (1977). London: Duckworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1986). Law’s Empire. London: Fontana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eemeren, van F. & Grootendorst. R. (1984). Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions: A Theoretical Model for the Analysis of Discussions Directed towards Solving Conflicts of Opinion. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E. (1999). Fundamentals of Legal Argumentation. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L. (1958). Positivism and the fidelity of law — A reply to Professor Hart. Harvard Law Review, 71: 630–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 1 (1981). Boston: McCarty.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987). The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 2 (1981). Boston, McCarty.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. (1958). Positivism and the separation of law and morality. Harvard Law Review, 71, 593–650.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. (1994). The Concept of Law (1961). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Torre, M. (1998). Teorie del’argomentazione giuridica e concetti di diritto. Un’approssimazione. Appendice all’edizione italiana di R. Alexy. Teoria dell’argomentazione giuridica (pp. 357–384). Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N.(1982). Legal Reasoning and Practical Reason. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 271–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. (1984). Legal Right and Social Democracy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. (1991). Donoghue v. Stevenson and legal reasoning. In P. Burns (Ed.), Donoghue v. Stevenson and the Modem Law of Negligence (pp. 191–213). Vancouver: Continuing Legal Education of British Columbia.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. (1993). Argumentation and interpretation in law. Ratio Juris, 16–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. (1994). Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory (1978). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N., & Weinberger, O. (1986). An Institutional Theory of Law. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (1992). Interpretation and Legal Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. (1989). On Law and Reason. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C. & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1958). La nouvelle rhéthorique. Traité de l’argumentation. Brussels: Edictions de l’Université de Brussels.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1972). Legal principles and the limits of law. The Yale Law Journal 81, 842–854.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1975). Practical Reason and Norms. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1979). The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1996). The Nature of Law. Archiv für Rechts-und Sozialphilosophie 82, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1958). The Uses of Arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldrom, J. (1992). The irrelevance of moral objectivity. In R. George (Ed.), Natural Law Theory (pp. 158–187). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski, J. (1974). Legal syllogism and rationality of judicial decision. Rechtstheorie, 14, 33–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski, J. (1992). The Judicial Application of Law. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bertea, S. (2003). Legal Argumentation Theory and the Concept of Law. In: Van Eemeren, F.H., Blair, J.A., Willard, C.A., Snoeck Henkemans, A.F. (eds) Anyone Who Has a View. Argumentation Library, vol 8. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1078-8_17

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1078-8_17

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-1456-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-1078-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics