Skip to main content

Overview

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 597 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory ((SNLT,volume 83))

Abstract

Set within the Chomskyan tradition, this book provides a typology of French Quantifiers (Qs, i.e. scope-bearing elements), based on their syntactic, semantic and prosodic behaviors.1 More specifically, the main issues are to investigate their nature(s), their meaning(s), as well as the dependency(ies) they enter into.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the time being, I use the term ‘quantifier’ (Q) to refer to items that contribute to some quantity or amount meaning. It does not say anything about its syntactic structure (or category), which is developed in Chapters 2, 3 and 4.

  2. 2.

    Originally Lewis 1975 bases the tripartite structure on adverbs of quantification.

  3. 3.

    In that respect, Hungarian resembles Japanese (see Lipták 2001): the ki-item is the basis of the quantificational paradigm, (i):

    (i)

    a.

    ki

    ‘who’

    c.

    minden-ki

    ‘everyone’

     

    b.

    vala-ki

    ‘someone’

    d.

    aki

    ‘whorel

  4. 4.

    Kayne 1975 identifies a second type of FQ constructions, with Q preceding the restriction, (i):

    (i)

    Elle a tous voulu les lire

     
     

    She has all wanted them to-read

     
     

    ‘She wanted to read them all’

    (Kayne 1975:4)

    This type is discussed in Section 3.1.3, when referring to Doetjes’ analysis of FQ constructions, and can then be analysed as a pure case of FQ structure, (19).

  5. 5.

    See Fitzpatrick 2006 for a non-uniform approach to the phenomenon: he argues that FQs are not all of the same type cross- (and inter-) linguistically. See also Chapter 3.

  6. 6.

    Cardinals, null Dets with bare nouns in English, partitives are also referred to as indefinites in the literature. In this section, I am only concerned with those mentioned in the main text.

  7. 7.

    Echo-questions must be distinguished from information-seeking questions in (22a). Echo-questions are confirmation, or repetition-seeking questions ‘or “any question said in immediate response to an utterance which is surprising, deserving repetition, or which was in part not heard, or thought not to have been heard correctly,” “[…] or a showing of politeness, or concern, or an expression of surprise or disbelief, or the like,”’ (Boeckx 1999:76). As such, echo-questions have a specific interpretation par excellence (Starke 2001). They have a particular prosody: they involve heavy stress of the wh in-situ (Mathieu 2002) or a ‘high + rising echo intonation’ (Boeckx 1999: 76, see also Mathieu 2002), which is, as I will develop below, crucially different from what information-seeking questions trigger.

  8. 8.

    In standard normative ‘written’ French, wh-fronting is never an option: it is compulsory and wh in-situ is rejected. In spoken French however, both are used.

  9. 9.

    This statement suggests a dichotomy between two ‘dialects' of French, i.e. between that of Chang 1997 (a.o) on the one hand and that of Starke 2001, Adli 2006, on the other hand. That there are indeed ‘two dialects' is not that clear: even if colloquial NSC French speakers can vary with respect to syntactic judgments (with both negative and scope islands), the variations are subtle and as such can be considered as one and a single dialect. As for SC French, the syntactic variations are less subtle and are clearly not homogenous (availability (or not) of wh in-situ with root infinitives, of modals etc), i.e. it should not be taken as a whole. My decision to split French into two dialects is not arbitrary, but relies on the stable observation that the in-situ strategy is or is not a root phenomenon for the authors discussed above. In Chapter 6, I suggest that the variations observed among speakers of different dialects is due to the way researchers tackle the phenomenon: in taking semantics and prosody into account or not.

  10. 10.

    I characterize indefinites as variables bound by an Existential Operator (∃) (Heim 1982).

  11. 11.

    Most of the influential works on French FQs focus on subject orientied tous ‘all’ (Kayne 1975, Sportiche 1988, Doetjes 1997 and Bobaljik 2003). Recently, Junker 1995, Kobuchi-Philip 2003 (and subsq.) and Fitzpatrick 2006 extend their analyses on FQ tous to FQ chacun ‘each’.

  12. 12.

    A reviewer points out that the arguments to leave chaque out of the discussion vanishes once English each is taken into account. Her remark lies on the fact that each floats, yet it does not take DP complements, each the student being ungrammatical. At first sight, this remark is relevant. Once we look in more details at the distribution of English each, things look more complex, yet. Puskás 2002 shows that each appears to have a mixed behavior, with a distribution varying from chaque to chacun: when each floats, its associate is a plural DP ((ib) vs (iib)). More importantly, when it does not float, of is inserted if the nominal is a DP plural ((ia) vs. (iia)):

    (i)

    a.

    Each of the architects should receive a prize.

     
     

    b.

    The architects should each receive a prize.

    (Puskás 2002: 124 (66))

    (ii)

    a.

    Each architect should receive a prize.

     
     

    b. *

    The architect should each receive a prize.

    (Puskás 2002: 124 (64))

    (i) and (ii) are is reminiscent of the distinction between chacun of-DP and chaque N: chacun takes a plural DP as its restriction (iii), while chaque a singular noun phrase (iv). only chacun can float:

    (iii)

    a.

    Chacun des architectes a reçu un prix.

     
      

    each of-the architects has received a prize

     
     

    b.

    Les architectes ont chacun reçu un prix.

     
      

    the architects have each received a prize

    (Puskás 2002: 124 (65))

    (iv)

    a.

    Chaque architecte a reçu un prix

     
      

    each architect has received a prize

     
     

    b. *

    L'architecte a chaque reçu un prix.

     
      

    the architect has each received a prize

    (Puskás 2002: 123 (63))

    These data suggest that each comes in two flavors: as a potential FQ (and as such takes the of-DP complement and corresponds to chacun), or as a determiner of the chaque-type (and as such, cannot float). Since English each is no more a counterexample to the arguments put forward above, leaving out chaque from the discussion is justified. For more details, see Puskás 2002.

  13. 13.

    This statement can be shown with other languages: in (i), the negative meaning is not morphologically marked (from Marcel den Dikken (p.c)): the negative semantics of the sentences in (i) are not due to morphological ‘negative’ marks: in (ia), n’t is not necessary to convey the negative meaning of the sentence; (ib) means ‘I do not care at all’ and in the Dutch example in (ic) de ballen ‘the balls’ turns the positive sentence negative when inserted.

    (i)

    a.

    I could(n’t) care less

     
      

    what do I care?!

     
     

    b.

    Ik snap er de ballen van

    (Dutch)

      

    I understand there the balls of

     
      

    ‘I do not understand it at all’

     
  14. 14.

    The term ‘external’ syntax is used to refer to syntactic operations at the level of the clause. ‘Internal’ syntax refers to operations occurring within a DP.

References

  • Abush, Dorit. 1994. The scope of indefinites. Natural Language Semantics 2:83–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adli, Aria. 2006. French wh-in-situ questions and syntactic optionality: Evidence from tree data types. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 25:163–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baunaz, Lena. 2005. The syntax and semantics of wh in-situ and existentials: The case of French. Leiden Working Papers in Linguistics 2.2. 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baunaz, Lena. 2008. Floating quantifiers: french universal quantifiers and N-words. In Selected Proceedings of the 34th Incontro di Grammatica Generativa, Special Issue of the Rivista di Grammatica Generativa, vol. 33. P. Beninca˛, F. Damonte and N. Penello (eds.). Padova: Unipress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Sigrid. 1996. Quantified structures as barriers for LF-movement. Natural Language Semantics 4:1–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beghelli, Fillipo. 1997. The syntax of distributivity and pair-list reading. In Ways of Scope Taking, Anna Szabolcsi (ed.), 349–408. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bobaljik, Jonathan. 2003. Floating quantifiers: Handle with care. In The Second Glot International State-of-The-Article Book, Lisa Cheng and Rint Sybesma (eds.), 107–148. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boeckx, Cédric. 1999. Decomposing French questions. In University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 6.1, Proceedings of the 23rd Annual Penn Linguistics Colloquium, J. Alexander, N.R. Han and M. Minnick Fox (eds.), 69–80. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bošković, Zeljiko. 2000. Sometimes in SpecCP, sometimes in-situ. In Step by Step: Essays on Minimalism in Honor of Howard Lasnik, Roger Martin, David Michaels and Juan Uriagereka (eds.), 53–87. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Lisa. 1997. Wh-in situ in French. MA thesis, University of British Colombia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, Lisa. 1991. On the Typology of Wh-questions. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT. Distributed by MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, Lisa and Johann Rooryck 2000. Licensing wh-in-situ. In Syntax 3 (1):1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corblin, Francis and Lucia Tovena 2003. L’expression de la négation dans les langues romanes. In Les langues romanes: problèmes de la phrase simple, Danièle Godard (ed.), 279–341. Paris: CNRS Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corblin, Francis, Vivian Déprez, Henriette de Swart and Luci Tovena. 2004. Negative concord. In Handbook of French Semantics, Francis Corblin and Henriette de Swart (eds.), 427–461. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Déprez, Viviane. 1997. Two Types of Negative Concord. Probus 9:103–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Déprez, Viviane. 2000. Parallels (A)symmetries and internal structure of negative expressions. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 18:253–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Déprez, Viviane. 2003. Concordance négative, syntaxe des mots-N et variation dialectale. Cahier de Linguistique Française 25:97–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diesing, Molly. 1992. Indefinites. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doetjes, Jenny. 1997. Quantifiers and Selection. On the Distribution of Quantifying Expressions in French, Dutch and English. Doctoral dissertation, HIL, Leiden University. The Hague: HAG.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enç, Mürvet. 1991. The semantics of specificity. Linguistic Inquiry 22:1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, Donka. 1994. Specificity and scope. In Langues et Grammaires 1, Lea Nash and George Tsoulas (eds.), 119–137. Paris: Universite Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, Donka. 2002. Specificity distinctions. Journal of Semantics 19:1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, Justin Michael. 2006. Syntactic and Semantic Routes to Floating Quantification. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry and Ivan Sag. 1982. Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy 5:355–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giannakidou, Anastasia. 1999. Affective dependencies. Linguistics and Philosophy 22:367–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giannakidou, Anastasia. 2000. Negative concord and the scope of universals. Transactions of the Philological Society 98:87–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haegeman, Liliane. 1995. The Syntax of Negation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haegeman, Liliane and Raffaela Zanuttini. 1991. Negative heads and the Neg criterion. The Linguistic Review 8:233–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagstrom, Paul. 1998. Decomposing Questions. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT. Distributed by MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagstrom, Paul. 2001. Particle movement in Sinhala and Japanese. In Clause Structure in South Asian Languages, Veneeta Dayal and Anoop Mahjan (eds.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 1982. The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, James. 1982. Move WH in a language without WH movement. The Linguistic Review 1:369–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ihsane, Tabea. 2008. The Layered DP. Form and Meaning of French Indefinites. Linguistik Aktuell/Linguistics Today 124. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Junker, Marie-Odile. 1995. Syntax et sémantique des quantifieurs flottants tous et chacun. Distributivité en sémantique conceptuelle. Genève: Librairie Droz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, Richard. 1975. French Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kobuchi-Philip, Mana. 2003. Distributivity and the Japanese Floating Numeral Quantifier. Ph.D. dissertation. City University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1975. Adverbs of quantification. In Formal Semantics of Natural Language, Edward Keenan (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipták, Aniko. 2001. On the Syntax of Wh-items in Hungarian. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Leiden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathieu, Eric. 2002. The Syntax of Non-Canonical Quantification: A Comparative Study. Doctoral dissertation, University College London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milsark, Gary. 1974. Existential Sentences in English. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT, published in 1979. New York-London: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Obenauer, Hans-Georg. 1992. L’interprétation des structures-wh et l’accord du partiticipe passé. In Structure de la Phrase et Théorie du Liage, Hans-Georg Obenauer and Anne Zribi-Hertz (eds.), 169–195. Saint-Denis: Presses Universitaires de Vincennes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Obenauer, Hans-Georg. 1994. Aspects de la Syntaxe A-Barre. Thèse de Doctorat d’Etat, Université de Paris VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pesetsky, David. 1987. Wh-in-situ: Movement and unselective binding. In The Representation of (In)definites, Eric Reuland and Alice ter Meulen (eds.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Puskás, Genoveva. 2000. Quantification in the left periphery: A syntactic argument for ‘split’ domains. In CLS 36, Volume 1: The Main Session, John Boyle, Jung-Huyck Lee and Arika Okrent (eds.). Chicago Linguistic Society: Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Puskás, Genoveva. 2002. Floating quantifiers: What they can tell us about the syntax and semantics of quantifiers. GG@G 3:105–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, Tanya. 1997. Quantifier scope. How labour is divided between QR and choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy 20:335–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzi, Luigi. 2002. The Structure of CP and IP. The Cartography of Syntactic Structures. Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shlonsky, Ur. 1991. Quantifiers as functional heads: A study of quantifier float in Hebrew. Lingua 84:159–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sportiche, Dominique. 1988. A Theory of floating quantifiers and its corrolaries for constituent structure. Linguistic Inquiry 19(3):425–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starke, Michal. 2001. Move Dissolves into Merge: A Theory of Locality. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Geneva.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Swart, Henriette and Ivan Sag 2002. Negation and negative concord in romance. Linguistics and Philosophy 25:373–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, Anna. 1997. Strategies for scope taking. In Ways of Scope Taking, Anna Szabolcsi (ed.). Dordrecht: Foris.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Watanabe, Akira. 1992. Subjacency and S-structure movement of wh-in-situ. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 1:255–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zanuttini, Raffaela. 1991. Syntactic Properties of Sentential Negation: A Comparative Study of Romance Languages. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lena Baunaz .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Baunaz, L. (2011). Overview. In: The Grammar of French Quantification. Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, vol 83. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0621-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics