Skip to main content

Scientific Knowledge and Structural Knowledge

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 990 Accesses

Part of the book series: The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 75))

Abstract

There is a very general question in the philosophy of science. It is this: how do we think our theories represent the world? What is theoretical knowledge in the sciences, knowledge of? One very influential answer to this question is the thesis of Structuralism: theoretical knowledge is not knowledge of unobservable objects and the hidden relations among them but is always and only knowledge of structure.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See (Ladyman and Ross, 2007). These are the main authors. The volume also contains contributions jointly written with James Ladyman and Dan Ross by David Spurrett and John Collier.

  2. 2.

    Thus they say explicitly, “It is not part of our realism that every time a scientist quantifies over something in formulation of a theory or hypothesis she is staking out an existential commitment …. Indeed, we will argue that, semantic appearances notwithstanding, we should not interpret science—either fundamental physics or special sciences—as metaphysically committed to the existence of self-subsistent individuals” (Ladyman and Ross, 2007, p. 119).

  3. 3.

    Kuhn loss was the supposed historical phenomenon that the explanatory successes of earlier theories at the level of successful predictions would fail to be captured by succeeding theories.

  4. 4.

    Van Fraassen in an excellent recent reply to structuralism (van Fraassen, 2006), gives a nice example of how observations reveal the structure of the phenomena behind them without revealing the qualities and inner nature of that hidden reality. His example is based on one provided by Russell in (Russell, 1927). Van Fraassen writes: “Listen to the radio, and hear the sounds which were produced in the studio many miles away. In between are the radio waves which have none of the qualities of sound. But we can infer that they must have structure which encodes the structure of this sound. Thus we know a great deal about those radio waves on the basis of observation: not what qualities they have or what they are like in themselves, but their structure. And it’s precisely that, and only that, which science describes (as it happens of course what Maxwell’s equations describe)”(p. 289).

  5. 5.

    The proof is straightforward. If an observation sentence O is not a consequence of T then some interpretation I of T satisfies T but fails to satisfy O. But then that same interpretation will satisfy R(T), since R(T) is merely an existential generalisation of some predicates in T, but will fail to satisfy O. So if O is a consequence of R(T) then it must be a consequence of T by contraposition. Similarly if O is not a consequence of R(T), then some interpretation of the existentially generalised predicates of T satisfies R(T) but fails to satisfy O. Precisely that interpretation of the predicates of T will then provide an interpretation of T itself which satisfies T but fails to satisfy O. Hence by contraposition if O is a consequence of T, O is a consequence of R(T). So as far as O-consequences are concerned T and R(T) are equivalent.

  6. 6.

    For proofs, see (Ketland, 2004; Demopoulos, 2008, 2003a). The background model theory is explained in (van Dalen, 1983).

  7. 7.

    Van Fraassen makes a closely related point. He puts the matter forcefully as follows: “if structure is not just there as mathematical or abstract entity, then it is not true that structure is all there is” (van Fraassen, 2006, p. 294).

Bibliography

  • Ainsworth, P. M. (2009). Newman’s objection. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 10:1–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1984). The current status of scientific realism. In Leplin, J., editor, Scientific Realism, pages 41–82. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dedekind, R. (1963). The Nature and Meaning of Numbers. Dover, New York, NY. Transl. W.W. Beman. Originally published 1887 as Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?

    Google Scholar 

  • Demopoulos, W. (2003a). On the rational reconstruction of our theoretical knowledge. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54:371–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demopoulos, W. (2003b). Russell’s structuralism and the absolute description of the world. In Griffin, N., editor, The Cambridge Companion to Russell, pages 392–419. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Demopoulos, W. (2007). Carnap on the rational reconstruction of scientific theories. In Creath, R. and Friedman, M., editors, The Cambridge Companion to Carnap, pages 248–272. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Demopoulos, W. (2008). Some remarks on the bearing of model theory on the theory of theories. Synthese, 164:359–383. (A special issue edited by Paolo Mancoscu dedicated to William Craig).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demopoulos, W. and Friedman, M. (1985). Russell’s Analysis of Matter: Its historical context and contemporary interest. Philosophy of science, 52:621–639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2001). How Things Persist. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. (2000). Hume’s Problem: Induction and the Justification of Belief. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ketland, J. (2004). Empirical adequacy and ramsification. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55:287–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. and Ross, D. (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M. H. A. (1928). Mr. Russell’s causal theory of perception. Mind, 37:137–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). What is mathematical truth? In Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, Volume 1, pages 60–78. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). The Principles of Mathematics. George Allen and Unwin, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1927). The Analysis of Matter. K. Paul, Trench, Trubner, London. Reprinted by Dover Books in 1954.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen, D. (1983). Logic and Structure. Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (2006). Structure: Its shadow and substance. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57:275–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds. Dialectica, 43:99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2007). Miracles and models: Why reports of the death of structural realism may be exaggerated. In Philosophy of Science, volume 61 of Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, pages 125–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahar, E. G. (2001). Poincaré’s Philosophy: from Conventionalism to Phenomenology. Open Court, Chicago and La Salle, IL.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Clark .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Clark, P. (2011). Scientific Knowledge and Structural Knowledge. In: DeVidi, D., Hallett, M., Clarke, P. (eds) Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy, Vintage Enthusiasms. The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 75. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0214-1_24

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics