Skip to main content

Two Approaches to Reasoning with Evidence: Arguments and Stories

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Arguments, Stories and Criminal Evidence

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 92))

  • 1083 Accesses

Abstract

The two types of reasoning that represent the main trends in the research on reasoning with criminal evidence. The first is argumentative reasoning, where the parties argue for and against the facts-at-issue using arguments based on evidence. The second type of reasoning is story-based or narrative reasoning, where the parties each provide alternative stories that explain the evidence. The advantages and disadvantages of each of the types of reasoning and the similarities and differences between them are also discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The case as presented here is a simplified account and deviates from Wagenaar and colleagues’ account on some points.

  2. 2.

    In Chapter 5, the idea of a set of arguments “defending” itself against attackers is made more clear through a series of formal definitions.

  3. 3.

    In Chapter 5, a formal dialogue game for a hybrid argumentative story-based theory will be provided.

  4. 4.

    This argument game is essentially an adapted version of (Prakken, 1997) .

  5. 5.

    Sherlock Holmes used these signs to explain that Watson was an army doctor (In Conan Doyle’s A Study in Scarlet).

  6. 6.

    In order to have a similar-looking scheme as the one for expert opinion given above, the abductive practical scheme presented here is of a slightly different form than the one in (Bex et al., 2009) .

  7. 7.

    In the Umilian chart (Wigmore, 1931, p. 56, see Fig. 7.4 in this book), node 9 is effectively a cause for node 8: J falsely charging U with bigamy caused a murderous emotion (in U) towards J. However, the scenario is here not properly separated from the argument and this combination of evidential and causal reasoning should be treated with care (cf. Pearl, 1988a).

  8. 8.

    In the remained of this chapter Pennington and Hastie will often be referred to without explicitly mentioning one of these articles.

  9. 9.

    Another well-known fallacy is cum hoc ergo propter hoc or correlation does not imply causation.

  10. 10.

    Twining (1999) calls these schemes “story types” or “scenarios”.

  11. 11.

    In this sense, a particular story can be likened to a case-specific generalization.

  12. 12.

    Just as a story can correspond to an abstract story scheme, a story can also correspond to a more abstract (but still case-specific) or more specific version of itself. For example, the event “Haaknat robs the supermarket” can be specified as “Haaknat threatens to use force against the owner of the supermarket” and “the owner of the supermarket hands over the money to Haaknat”.

  13. 13.

    Exactly what constitutes a proper or a good story will be discussed in Section 3.2.4.

  14. 14.

    Twining (1999) , however, argues that stories are not always necessary. In many criminal cases there is only one fact at issue and complex hypotheses involving motives and actions need not be considered.

  15. 15.

    In this sense, stories play a big psychological role (Anderson et al., 2005) , as opposed to the more atomistic arguments, which play a more logical role.

  16. 16.

    Wigmore argued that the (argumentative) chart method is the only “thorough and scientific method” for analysing evidence.

References

  • Amgoud, L. and Cayrol, C. (2002) A reasoning model based on the production of acceptable arguments. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 34:1, 97–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, T.J., Schum, D.A. and Twining, W.L. (2005) Analysis of Evidence, 2nd edition, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bal, M. (1985) Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative, University of Toronto Press, Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, W.L. and Feldman, M.S. (1981) Reconstructing Reality in the Courtroom: Justice and Judgment in American Culture, Methuen – Tavistock, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J. (2009) Analysing stories using schemes. In Kaptein, H., Prakken, H. and Verheij B. (eds.), Legal Evidence and Proof: Statistics, Stories, Logic, 93–116, Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., Bench-Capon, T. and Atkinson, K. (2009) Did he jump or was he pushed? abductive practical reasoning. Artificial Intelligence and Law 17:2, 79–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., Braak, S.W. van den, Oostendorp, H. van, Prakken, H., Verheij, B. and Vreeswijk, G. (2007b) Sense – making software for crime investigation: how to combine stories and arguments? Law, Probability and Risk 6, 145–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J. and Prakken, H (2004) Reinterpreting arguments in dialogue: an application to evidential reasoning. JURIX 2004: The 17th Annual Conference, 119–129, IOS Press, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., Prakken, H., Reed, C. and Walton, D.N. (2003) Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: argumentation schemes and generalisations. Artificial Intelligence and Law 11, 125–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J. and Verheij, B. (2009) Het onderbouwen van een feitelijk oordeel in een strafzaak: methode, casus, aanbevelingen (Grounding a judgement about the facts in a criminal case: method, case, recommendations). In Van Koppen, P.J., Merkelbach, H., Jelicic, M., and de Keijser, J.W. (eds.), Reizen Met Mijn Rechter: Psychologie Van Het Recht, Kluwer, Deventer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braak, S.W. van den, Oostendorp, H. van, Vreeswijk, G. and Prakken, H. (2008) Representing Narrative and Testimonial Knowledge in Sense – making Software for Crime Analysis. JURIX 2008: The 21st Annual Conference, 160–169, IOS Press, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braak, S.W. van den, Oostendorp, H. van, Prakken, H. and Vreeswijk, G.A.W. (2006) A critical review of argument visualization tools: do users become better reasoners. ECAI06: Workshop on Computational Models of Natural Argument. Trento

    Google Scholar 

  • Chesñevar, C.I., Maguitman, A.G. and Loui, R.P. (2000) Logical models of argument. ACM Computing Surveys (CSUR) 32:4, 337–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L.J. (1977) The Probable and The Provable, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Console, L. and Torasso, P. (1991) A spectrum of logical definitions of model – based diagnosis. Computational Intelligence 7:3, 133–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crombag, H.F.M. and Israëls, H. (2008) Moord in AnjumTe veel niet gestelde vragen, Boom Juridische Uitgevers, Den Haag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crombag, H.F.M., Wagenaar, W.A. and Koppen, P.J. van. (1994) Dubieuze Zaken: De Psychologie van Strafrechtelijk Bewijs, 2nd edition, Contact, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Poot, C.J., Bokhorst, R.J., Koppen, P.J. van and Muller, E.R. (2004) Rechercheportret – Over Dillemma’s in de Opsporing, Kluwer, Alphen a.d. Rijn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dingley, A.M. (1999) The ballpoint case: a wigmorean analysis. In Nijboer, J.F. and Malsch, M. (eds.), Complex Cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands Criminal Justice System, 179–188, Thela Thesis, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dung, P.M. (1995) On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming and n – person games. Artificial Intelligence 77:2, 321–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. and Sebeok, T.A. (1983) The Sign of Three: Dupin, Holmes, Pierce, Indiana University Press, Bloomington (Indiana).

    Google Scholar 

  • Eemeren, F.H. van and Grootendorst, R. (2004) A Systematic Theory of Argumentation: The Pragma – Dialectical Approach, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einhorn, H.J. and Hogarth, R.M. (1986) Judging probable cause. Psychological Bulletin. 99:1, 3–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E.T. (1999) What went wrong in the ballpoint case?. In Malsch, M. and Nijboer, J.F. (eds.), Complex Cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands Criminal Justice System, 159–179, Thela Thesis, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J.B. (1991) Dialectics and the Macrostructure of Arguments: A Theory of Argument Structure, Foris Publications, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, T.F., Prakken, H. and Walton, D. (2007) The Carneades model of argument and burden of proof. Artificial Intelligence 171:10–15, 875–896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heuer, R.J. (1999) Psychology of Intelligence Analysis, Center for the Study of Intelligence, Central Intelligence Agency.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1888) A treatise of human nature. In Selby–Bigge, L.A. (eds.), Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, N.S. and Mandler, J.M. (1980) A tale of two structures: Underlying and surface forms in stories. Poetics 9, 51–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J.R. (2002) On the proof dynamics of inference to the best explanation. In MacCrimmon, M. and Tillers, P. (eds.), The Dynamics of Judicial Proof – Computation, Logic and Common Sense, 287–306, Physica Verlag, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J.R. and Josephson, S.G. (1994) Abductive Inference: Computiation, Philosophy, Technology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kadane, J.B. and Schum, D.A. (1996) A Probabilistic Analysis of the Sacco and Vanzetti Evidence, Wiley, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerstholt, J.H. and Eikelboom, A.R. (2007) Effects of prior interpretation on situation assessment in crime analysis. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 20:5, 455–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knigge, G. (2001) Leerstukken Van Het Strafprocesrecht, 5th edition, Kluwer, Deventer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loui, R.P. (1987) Defeat among arguments: a system of defeasible inference. Computational Intelligence 3:1, 100–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loui, R.P. (1998) Process and policy: resource – bounded nondemonstrative reasoning. Computational Intelligence 14:1, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loui, R.P. and Norman, J. (1995) Rationales and argument moves. Artificial Intelligence and Law 3:3, 159–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, P. (1997) Symbolic diagnosis and its formalisation. The Knowledge Engineering Review 12, 109–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malsch, M. and Freckelton, I. (2009) The evaluation of evidence: differences between legal systems. In Kaptein, H., Prakken, H., and Verheij, B. (eds.), Legal Evidence and Proof: Statistics, Stories, Logic, 117–134, Ashgate, Aldershot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, J.M. and Johnson, N.S. (1977) Remembrance of things parsed: Story structure and recall. Cognitive Psychology 9, 111–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Modgil, S. (2007) An abstract theory of argumentation that accommodates defeasible reasoning about preferences. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 4724: 648–659, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nijboer, J.F. (1993) Common law tradition in evidence scholarship observed from a continental perspective. The American Journal of Comparative Law 51:2, 299–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pardo, M.S. and Allen, R.J. (2007) Juridical proof and the best explanation. Law and Philosophy 27, 223–268. Springer.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (1988a) Embracing causality in default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence 35, 259–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, N. and Hastie, R. (1986) Evidence evaluation in complex decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 51, 242–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, N. and Hastie, R. (1988) Explanation – based decision making: effects of memory structure on judgment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 14:3, 521–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, N. and Hastie, R. (1992) Explaining the evidence: tests of the story model for juror decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 62:2, 189–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, N. and Hastie, R. (1993a) Reasoning in explanation – based decision making. Cognition 49:1–2, 123–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, N. and Hastie, R. (1993b) The story model for juror decision making. In Hastie, R. (eds.), Inside the Juror: The Psychology of Juror Decision Making, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J.L. (1987) Defeasible reasoning. Cognitive Science 11:4, 481–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J.L. (1995) Cognitive Carpentry: A Blueprint for How to Build a Person, MIT Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (1997) Logical Tools for Modelling Legal Argument, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (2005a) A study of accrual of arguments, with applications to evidential reasoning. Proceedings of the 10th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 85–94, ACM, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (2006) Formal systems for persuasion dialogue. The Knowledge Engineering Review 21:02, 163–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. and Sartor, G. (1997) Argument – based extended logic programming with defeasible priorities. Journal of Applied Non – classical Logics 7, 25–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. and Vreeswijk, G. (2002) Logics for defeasible argumentation. In Goebel, R. and Guenthner, F. (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 219–318, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Propp, V. (1968) The Morphology of the Folktale, University of Texas Press, Austin (Texas).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1977) Dialectics: A ControversyOriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge, State University of New York Press, Albany (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rider, Y. and Thomason, N. (2008) Cognitive and pedagogical benefits of argument mapping: L.A.M.P. guides the way to better thinking. In Okada, A., Buckingham Shum, S. and Sherborne, T. (eds.), Knowledge Cartography: Software Tools and Mapping Techniques, Springer, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D.E. (1975) Notes on a schema for stories. In Bobrow, D.G. and Collins, A. (eds.), Representation and Understanding: Studies in Cognitive Science, Academic Press, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R.C. (1975) The structure of episodes in memory. In D. Bobrow and A. Collins (eds.), Representation and Understanding: Studies in Cognitive Science, 235–259, Academic Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R.C. (1986) Explanations Patterns: Understanding Mechanically and Creatively, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale (New Jersey).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R.C. and Abelson, R.P. (1977) Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding: an Inquiry into Human Knowledge Structures, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale (New Jersey).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D.A. (1994) The Evidential Foundations of Probabilistic Reasoning, Northwestern University Press, Evanston (Illinois).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D.A. (2001) Species of abductive reasoning in fact investigation in law. Cardozo Law Review 22, 1645–1681.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D.A. (2005) Narratives in Intelligence Analysis: Necessary but Often Dangerous, Evidence Research, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanahan, M. (1989) Prediction is deduction but explanation is abduction. Proceedings of International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence 89, 1055–1060.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D. (2001) A third view of the black box: cognitive coherence in legal decision making. University of Chicago Law Review 71, 511–586.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, N.L. and Glenn, C.G. (1979) An analysis of story comprehension in elementary school children. New directions in discourse processing 2, 53–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2004) Causal inference in legal decision making: explanatory coherence vs. bayesian networks. Applied Artificial Intelligence 18:3, 231–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2005) Testimony, credibility, and explanatory coherence. Erkenntnis 63:3, 295–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tillers, P. (2005) Picturing Inference, Gerechtigkeitswissenschaft, Berliner Wissenschafts–Verlag, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toolan, M. (2001) Narrative: A Critical Linguistic Introduction, 2nd edition, Routledge, London, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S.E. (2003) The Uses of Argument, Updated edition, (originally published in 1958), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trabasso, T. and Sperry, L.L. (1985) Causal relatedness and importance of story events. Journal of Memory and Language 24:5, 595–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Twardy, C. (2004) Argument maps improve critical thinking. Teaching Philosophy 27:2, 95–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining, W.L. (1999) Necessary but dangerous? generalizations and narrative in argumentation about “facts” in criminal process. In Nijboer, J.F. and Malsch, M. (eds.), Complex Cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands Criminal Justice System, 69–98, Thela Thesis, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining, W.L. (2006) Rethinking Evidence: Exploratory Essays, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2003b) Dialectical argumentation with argumentation schemes: an approach to legal logic. Artificial Intelligence and Law 11:2, 167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vreeswijk, G. (1993) Defeasible dialectics: A controversy – oriented approach towards defeasible argumentation. Journal of Logic and Computation 3:3, 317–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagenaar, W.A., Koppen, P.J. van and Crombag, H.F.M. (1993) Anchored Narratives: The Psychology of Criminal Evidence, St. Martin’s Press, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. (1998) The New Dialectic: Conversational Contexts of Argument, University of Toronto Press, Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. and Schafer, B. (2006) Arthur, George and the mystery of the missing motive: towards a theory of evidentiary reasoning about motives. International Commentary on Evidence 4:2, 1–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. (1996) Argumentation Schemes for Presumptive Reasoning, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah (New Jersey).

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. (2002) Legal Argumentation and Evidence, Penn, State University Press, University Park (Pennsylvania).

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. and Krabbe, E.C.W. (1995) Commitment in Dialogue, State University of New York Press, Albany (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., Reed, C. and Macagno, F. (2008) Argumentation Schemes, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, W.H., Nicholas, D.W. and Trabasso, T. (1979) Event chains and inferences in understanding narratives. New directions in discourse processing 2, 23–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigmore, J.H. (1931) The Principles of Judicial Proof or the Process of Proof as Given by Logic, Psychology, and General Experience, and Illustrated in Judicial Trials, 2nd edition, Little, Brown and Company, Boston (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wyner, A., Bench-Capon, T.J.M. and Atkinson, K. (2008) Three senses of argument. In Sartor, G. (eds.), Computable Models of the Law: Languages, Dialogues, Games, Ontologies, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C. and Rowe, G. (2004) Araucaria: software for argument diagramming, analysis and representation. International Journal of AI Tools 13, 961–980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, K., Bench-Capon, T. and McBurney, P. (2006) Computational representation of practical argument. Synthese 152:2, 157–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (2005) Poetics. In Butcher, S.H. (eds.), Wordplay Archives, http://wordplayer.com/archives/poetics.txt

  • Trabasso, T. and Broek, P. van den. (1985) Causal thinking and the representation of narrative events. Journal of Memory and Language 24:5, 612–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. and Shelley, C.P. (1997) Abductive reasoning: logic, visual thinking, and coherence. In Dalla Chiara, M.L. (eds.), Logic and Scientific methods, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Floris J. Bex .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bex, F.J. (2011). Two Approaches to Reasoning with Evidence: Arguments and Stories. In: Arguments, Stories and Criminal Evidence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 92. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0140-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics