Skip to main content

Reasoning with Criminal Evidence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Arguments, Stories and Criminal Evidence

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 92))

  • 1090 Accesses

Abstract

Abstract The process of proof, reasoning with evidence and commonsense knowledge in order to establish the facts of the case. Some general concepts that are important in this process are clarified and some general subjects (e.g. types of evidence) are discussed in detail. The chapter also discusses the types of reasoning that play an important role in the process (e.g. abductive reasoning, causal reasoning, defeasible reasoning).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This interpretation of the term fact is evident in the Dutch Code of Criminal Proceedings, which states that “the court deliberates […] whether it is proved that the facts were perpetrated by the suspect […] ” (article 350 DCCP) .

  2. 2.

    State v. Famber, 358 Mo. 288, 293, 214 S.W.2d 40, 43.

  3. 3.

    Stern v. Employers’ Liability Assur. Corp., Ltd. Of London, England, 249 S.W. 739, 741.

  4. 4.

    “circumstantial evidence”, Oxford Dictionary of Law. Ed. Elizabeth A. Martin and Jonathan Law. Oxford University Press, 2006. Oxford Reference Online. Oxford University Press. Accessed on 15th July 2008.

    http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&entry=t49e613

  5. 5.

    In fact, the Dutch criminal procedure relies almost solely on documents.

  6. 6.

    The term “generalizations” is also used by Anderson, Schum and Twining (e.g. Anderson, 1999; Anderson et al., 2005; Twining, 1999) . Wagenaar and colleagues (1993) use the term “common-sense rules”.

  7. 7.

    In the rest of this thesis, the term “generalization” is used for commonsense statements of both a conditional and non-conditional form, keeping in mind that it is in theory always possible to rewrite a generalization as a conditional rule (see also Section 5.1.).

  8. 8.

    Here I use the general term “hypothesis”. Such a hypothesis can have various forms (e.g. a hypothetical scenario, the identity of a person’s whose blood was found and so on). Below the specific process of proof for crime investigation will be briefly discussed.

  9. 9.

    Wigmore characterizes a proof as “the persuasive operation of the total mass of evidentiary facts, as to a probandum” (Wigmore, 1931, p. 9) . The important parallel with the current conception of proof is that the total mass of evidence that pertains to a hypothesis is considered in a proof.

  10. 10.

    In the overarching process of proof in crime investigation, hypotheses can be equated with scenarios. However, other hypotheses are also important in any of the “sub-processes of proof”. For example, a hypothesis can also concern the identity of the possible perpetrator or the exact time of death and each of these individual hypotheses needs to be tested before they can be incorporated in the main scenario.

  11. 11.

    Dutch law (art. 338 and 350 DCCP) says that the judge should determine whether the suspect committed the acts as given in the indictment.

  12. 12.

    The term “defeasibility” seems to have been introduced in legal philosophy by Hart (cf. Loui, 1995) , who argued that a legal concept (e.g. “contract”) not only encompasses the positive conditions which have to be met (e.g. there has to be an offer and acceptance of the offer) but also that which can defeat the claim that we are dealing with the appropriate legal concept (e.g. the parties hold a mistaken belief of the facts).

  13. 13.

    Van Eemeren and colleagues (1996) characterize dialectic as “the art of arguing for and against”.

  14. 14.

    The triangle is often attributed to Peirce, see (Burch, 2008) and (Peirce, 1931) .

  15. 15.

    This last term is by Gabbay and Woods (2006) , who also contrast it with deductive reasoning, which they call truth-preserving and induction, which they call likelihood-enhancing.

  16. 16.

    I do not consider abduction and IBE to be one and the same. Abduction involves solely the creation of new hypotheses, whereas IBE is also about testing and comparing hypotheses.

  17. 17.

    Note that Poole, Mackworth and Goebel’s (1997) distinction between causal and evidential reasoning is different from the one presented here. Their evidential reasoning is essentially what is here called explanatory reasoning and their causal reasoning is what is here called predictive reasoning.

  18. 18.

    It can be argued that this is only the case when c is a typical cause of e.

  19. 19.

    In Bex et al., 2009, motives were equated with values (cf. Bench-Capon, 2003) , which are also abstract principles that can be promoted or demoted.

References

  • Anderson, T.J. (1999) On generalizations I: A preliminary exploration. South Texas Law Review 40, p. 455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, T.J., Schum, D.A. and Twining, W.L. (2005) Analysis of Evidence, 2nd edition, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bench-Capon, T.J.M. (2003) Persuasion in practical argument using value – based argumentation frameworks. Journal of Logic and Computation 13:3, 429–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., Bench-Capon, T. and Atkinson, K. (2009) Did he jump or was he pushed? abductive practical reasoning. Artificial Intelligence and Law 17:2, 79–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burch, R. (2008) Charles sanders peirce, In Zalta, E.N. (eds.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2008 edition, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/peirce/

  • Cohen, L.J. (1977) The Probable and The Provable, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Console, L., Dupré, D.T. and Torasso, P. (1991) On the relationship between abduction and deduction. Journal of Logic and Computation 1, 661–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crombag, H.F.M., Wagenaar, W.A. and Koppen, P.J. van. (1994) Dubieuze Zaken: De Psychologie van Strafrechtelijk Bewijs, 2nd edition, Contact, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Poot, C.J., Bokhorst, R.J., Koppen, P.J. van and Muller, E.R. (2004) Rechercheportret – Over Dillemma’s in de Opsporing, Kluwer, Alphen a.d. Rijn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D.C. (1978) Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology, MIT press, Cambridge (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. and Sebeok, T.A. (1983) The Sign of Three: Dupin, Holmes, Pierce, Indiana University Press, Bloomington (Indiana).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D.M. and Woods, J. (2006) Advice on Abductive Logic, 14th edition, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N.R. (1962) Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science, The Scientific Book Guild, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hielkema, J. (1999) Experts in dutch criminal procedure. In Malsch, M. and Nijboer, J.F. (eds.), Complex Cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands Criminal Justice System, 27–46, Thela Thesis, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J.R. (2002) On the proof dynamics of inference to the best explanation. In MacCrimmon, M. and Tillers, P. (eds.), The Dynamics of Judicial Proof – Computation, Logic and Common Sense, 287–306, Physica Verlag, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J.R. and Josephson, S.G. (1994) Abductive Inference: Computiation, Philosophy, Technology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kerstholt, J.H. and Eikelboom, A.R. (2007) Effects of prior interpretation on situation assessment in crime analysis. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 20:5, 455–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E.F. (1996) Eyewitness Testimony, 2nd edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Loui, R.P. (1995) Hart’s critics on defeasible concepts and ascriptivism. Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 21–30, ACM Press, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nijboer, J.F. (2000) Strafrechtelijk Bewijsrecht, 4th edition, Ars Aequi Libri, Nijmegen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nijboer, J.F. and Sennef, A. (1999) Justification. In Nijboer, J.F. and Malsch, M. (eds.), Complex Cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands Criminal Justice System, 11–26, Thela Thesis, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pardo, M.S. and Allen, R.J. (2007) Juridical proof and the best explanation. Law and Philosophy 27, 223–268. Springer.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (1988a) Embracing causality in default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence 35, 259–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S. (1931) Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P., and Burks, A. (eds.), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H.F.G. (1978) Reichenbach, M. and Cohen, R.S. (eds.), Selected Writings: 1909–1953, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1977) Dialectics: A ControversyOriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge, State University of New York Press, Albany (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R.C. (1986) Explanations Patterns: Understanding Mechanically and Creatively, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale (New Jersey).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D.A. (1994) The Evidential Foundations of Probabilistic Reasoning, Northwestern University Press, Evanston (Illinois).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D.A. (2001) Species of abductive reasoning in fact investigation in law. Cardozo Law Review 22, 1645–1681.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanahan, M. (1989) Prediction is deduction but explanation is abduction. Proceedings of International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence 89, 1055–1060.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D. (2001) A third view of the black box: cognitive coherence in legal decision making. University of Chicago Law Review 71, 511–586.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1988) Computational Philosophy of Science, MIT Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1989) Explanatory coherence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12:3, 435–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2004) Causal inference in legal decision making: explanatory coherence vs. bayesian networks. Applied Artificial Intelligence 18:3, 231–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Twining, W.L. (1999) Necessary but dangerous? generalizations and narrative in argumentation about “facts” in criminal process. In Nijboer, J.F. and Malsch, M. (eds.), Complex Cases: Perspectives on the Netherlands Criminal Justice System, 69–98, Thela Thesis, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining, W.L. (2006) Rethinking Evidence: Exploratory Essays, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (1999) Automated argument assistance for lawyers. Proceedings of the 7th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 43–52, ACM New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2003b) Dialectical argumentation with argumentation schemes: an approach to legal logic. Artificial Intelligence and Law 11:2, 167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagenaar, W.A., Koppen, P.J. van and Crombag, H.F.M. (1993) Anchored Narratives: The Psychology of Criminal Evidence, St. Martin’s Press, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. (2001) Abductive, presumptive and plausible arguments. Informal Logic 21:2, 141–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. and Schafer, B. (2006) Arthur, George and the mystery of the missing motive: towards a theory of evidentiary reasoning about motives. International Commentary on Evidence 4:2, 1–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigmore, J.H. (1931) The Principles of Judicial Proof or the Process of Proof as Given by Logic, Psychology, and General Experience, and Illustrated in Judicial Trials, 2nd edition, Little, Brown and Company, Boston (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S.E. (1958) The Uses of Argument, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S.E. (2003) The Uses of Argument, Updated edition, (originally published in 1958), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. (1996) Argumentation Schemes for Presumptive Reasoning, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah (New Jersey).

    Google Scholar 

  • Eemeren, F.H. van, Grootendorst, R., Henkemans, F.S., Blair, J.A., Johnson, R.H., Krabbe, E.C.W., Plantin, C., Walton, D.N., Willard, C.A. and Woods, J. (1996) Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale (New Jersey).

    Google Scholar 

  • Poole, D., Mackworth, A. and Goebel, R. (1997) Computational Intelligence: A Logical Approach, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. and Ulian, J. (1970) The Web of Belief, Random House, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiter, R. (1980) A logic for default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence 13, 81–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Floris J. Bex .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bex, F.J. (2011). Reasoning with Criminal Evidence. In: Arguments, Stories and Criminal Evidence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 92. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0140-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics