Skip to main content

Degradation: A Human Rights Law Perspective

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Humiliation, Degradation, Dehumanization

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 24))

Abstract

This chapter focuses on a number of common questions relating to the concept of degradation, against the backdrop of that concept as it has developed in the jurisprudence of the European Convention on Human Rights, specifically in relation to the prohibition of degrading treatment within Article 3. The prohibition of torture and inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment is commonly understood, and is expressed in case-law, as having an intimate connection with the concept of human dignity, the language of which underpins the modern human rights regime. The basic structure of the Article 3 understanding of degradation is outlined, alongside examples of its practical application, in order to highlight significant conceptual relationships. Questions concerning the significance of the individual emotion of degradation, the relevance of autonomy in understanding degradation, and the relevance of the idea of social dignity can be illuminated by a contextualized discussion of the jurisprudence. It is suggested in this respect that the scope of what can be understood as degradation is not limited primarily by the victim’s emotional experience, that the jurisprudence draws our attention to one particular facet of autonomy, and that the essence of the concept of degradation is helpfully captured in the idea of abuse of equal rank.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Some reference will also be made to the former European Commission of Human Rights, although examples will primarily be drawn from the legally binding decisions of the Court.

  2. 2.

    The Compact Edition of the Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford: Clarendon Press (all dictionary references in the present chapter refer to this edition unless otherwise stated).

  3. 3.

    See the work of Peter Cane in the context of the concept of responsibility, which is illuminative in this respect. Cane discusses the particular value of common law approaches to responsibility, deriving from the uniqueness of the institutional legal setting, for understanding responsibility beyond law as a complex moral concept (Cane 2002: 9–28). I would like to thank my colleague Simon Halliday for drawing the work of Cane to my attention.

  4. 4.

    This is visible, for example, in an article on degrading treatment entitled “The Limits of Degradation and Respect” (Lawson and Mukherjee 2004) and in an article entitled “Punishment, Dignity and Degradation” (Duff 2005). See also Susan Millns’ reference to dignity and degradation as two sides of the same coin (Millns 2002).

  5. 5.

    Ireland v. United Kingdom, 18 January 1978, Series A, no. 25, para. 167.

  6. 6.

    Greek Case, Commission Report of 5 November 1969, Yearbook of the European Convention on Human Rights XII (1969), Chapter IV, section A(2), p. 186; Keenan v. United Kingdom, no. 27229/95, ECHR 2001-III.

  7. 7.

    Abdulaziz, Cabales and Balkandali v. United Kingdom, 28 May 1985, Series A, no. 94, para. 91.

  8. 8.

    This is unsurprising; such elaboration is not to be expected given that the Court is primarily concerned, now that the principles are firmly established, with the concrete application of the law to very particular facts in concrete complaints before it. Martha Nussbaum makes this point in relation to a jury deciding upon a case involving emotions, where a more general exploration of the emotional concepts involved is not an immediate concern (Nussbaum 2004: 67–68).

  9. 9.

    Applicants have often argued, and the ECtHR has arrived at, conclusions of inhuman and degrading treatment (for example, in Ireland v. UK). However, a distinction between “inhuman” and “degrading” is evident where the ECtHR classifies treatment or punishment specifically as one form or the other (see, for example, Yankov v. Bulgaria, no. 39084/97, ECHR 2003-VII (degrading treatment) and Bilgin v. Turkey, no. 23819/94, 16 November 2000 (inhuman treatment)), and it is also visible in the different conceptual points of reference that have been established by the ECtHR.

  10. 10.

    The case-law research on which this chapter is based focuses primarily on outcomes of degrading treatment, rather than punishment, in cases before the Court. Judgments of degrading treatment are more common than those on punishment, notably since treatment appears to be the broader of the two terms and capable of also encompassing punishment. This is suggested by Nowak in the context of the equivalent provision of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (Nowak 2005: 159; Jayawickrama 2002: 303). Where helpful insight is provided, however, specific punishment cases will also be cited. For present purposes, it is not significant whether degradation takes the form of treatment or punishment; what is significant is the understanding of the degrading nature of the treatment or punishment.

  11. 11.

    E.g. Kalashnikov v. Russia, no. 47095/99, ECHR 2002-VI, para. 97–102; Peers v. Greece, no. 28525/95, ECHR 2001-III, para. 72–75.

  12. 12.

    Barbu Anghelescu v.Romania, no. 46430/99, 05 October 2004, para. 55–60.

  13. 13.

    Valasinas v. Lithuania, no. 44558/98, ECHR 2001-VIII, para. 117.

  14. 14.

    Nevmerzhitsky v. Ukraine, no. 54825/00, ECHR 2005-II. para. 100–106.

  15. 15.

    Tyrer v. United Kingdom, judgment of 25 April 1978, Series A, no. 26.

  16. 16.

    Yankov v. Bulgaria, para. 112–113.

  17. 17.

    Smith and Grady v. United Kingdom, no. 33985/96; 33986/96, ECHR 1999-VI, para. 121. See also the comments of the European Commission of Human Rights in East African Asians v. United Kingdom, Commission Report of 14 December 1973, Decisions and Reports 31, para. 207.

  18. 18.

    The “minimum level of severity” is a standard requirement that is referred to systematically in Article 3 case-law; see Ireland v. United Kingdom, para. 162.

  19. 19.

    López Ostra v. Spain, judgment of 09 December 1994, Series A, no. 303-C, para. 60.

  20. 20.

    Ireland v. United Kingdom, para. 162.

  21. 21.

    Guzzardi v. Italy, judgment of 06 November 1980, Series A, no. 39, para. 107.

  22. 22.

    Iwanczuk v. Poland, no. 25196/94, 15 November 2001, para. 59.

  23. 23.

    Keenan v. UK, no. 27229/95, ECHR 2001-III, para. 113.

  24. 24.

    Price v. United Kingdom, no. 33394/96, ECHR 2001-VII.

  25. 25.

    Peers v. Greece, no. 28524/95, ECHR 2001-V; Valasinas v. Lithuania, no. 44558/98, ECHR 2001-VIII.

  26. 26.

    Tyrer v. United Kingdom.

  27. 27.

    Humiliation is coupled in the standard characterization with debasement. The latter appears to act primarily as reinforcement. Principally, it provides a strong link to the concept of degradation in its visible sharing of the “de” preposition, highlighting the “down from”, “off” dimension of the concept. Debasement is found in one dictionary defined simply as degradation (The Chambers English Dictionary. Cambridge: Chambers). Humiliation instead emerges as the core concept within this coupling.

  28. 28.

    Tyrer v. United Kingdom, para. 32

  29. 29.

    On the concept of humiliation, see Chapters 3 by Neuhäuser and Chapter 4 by Kuch (this volume).

  30. 30.

    Campbell and Cosans v. United Kingdom, judgment of 25 February 1982, Series A, no. 48, para. 28–30.

  31. 31.

    Furthermore, the emotion/social fact distinction helps to explain the logic of a related principle that is found in the Court’s case-law: that humiliation does not need to have been intentionally inflicted; see T. v. United Kingdom, no. 24724/94, 16 December 1999, para. 69. The emotion/social fact distinction contributes a justification for this position, simply in that the distinction makes possible the independence of the emotion and the social fact: The Court reserves to itself the ability to identify a state of humiliation that is not wholly dependent upon perceptions of either the “humiliator” or the victim. In the case of Farbtuhs v. Latvia, the Court reached a finding of degrading treatment despite both the Court and the applicant acknowledging that there had been no intention to humiliate; Farbtuhs v. Latvia, no. 4672/02, 02 December 2004, para. 58.

  32. 32.

    In Rawls’ discussion of public reason, see note 23 on differences and similarities to Dworkin’s political morality (Rawls 1993: 236–237). See also Dworkin (2006: 251–254) for a brief discussion.

  33. 33.

    This view of adjudication embeds the possibility of judges arriving at different decisions on the basis of their own readings of the community morality (Dworkin 1977: 128). For further discussion, see Dworkin (2003: 67–111).

  34. 34.

    Ireland v. United Kingdom, Commission Report of 25 January 1976, Decisions and Reports 31, 402.

  35. 35.

    As noted above, the concept of autonomy is commonly viewed as relevant to understanding human dignity. Also common is a concern with the implications of a dependent link between dignity and autonomy – if dignity is violated by restriction of autonomy, what are the implications of this for those who are designated as lacking autonomy? This is an important question, yet one that is hindered by a lack of precision in how the terms are employed. The implications of such an objection depend upon what is understood by autonomy (including when, why, and by whom certain human beings are labeled as non-autonomous in some sense), upon how dignity itself is understood, and upon how the nature of the link between autonomy and dignity is viewed. Nevertheless, it can be noted in the context of the above example that there is no necessary implication that violations of dignity in the form of degradation are always characterized by restriction of the capacity for autonomy.

  36. 36.

    Attributed on the basis of social position or role; see Pollmann (Chapter 17, this volume) for a brief summary of the origins of this conception.

  37. 37.

    Peers v. Greece, para. 75.

  38. 38.

    East African Asians, Commission Report, para. 189.

  39. 39.

    An indicator of degradation that had in the meantime been established by the Court.

  40. 40.

    Raninen v. Finland, no. 20972/92, Commission Report of 24 October 1996, para. 50-52; Raninen v. Finland, no. 20972/92, 16 December 1997, Reports 1997-VIII, para. 55.

  41. 41.

    Raninen v. Finland, para. 54 (emphasis added).

  42. 42.

    Waldron has also recently engaged, in what is a rare discussion, with the idea of degradation; see Waldron (2008).

References

  • Abdulaziz, Cabales and Balkandali v. United Kingdom, judgment of 28 May 1985, Series A, no. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbu Anghelescu v. Romania, no. 46430/99, 05 October 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilgin v. Turkey, no. 23819/94, 16 November 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell and Cosans v. United Kingdom, judgment of 25 February 1982, Series A, no. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  • East African Asians v. United Kingdom, Commission Report of 14 December 1973, Decisions and Reports 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farbtuhs v. Latvia, no. 4672/02, 02 December 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greek Case, Commission Report, 5 November 1969, Yearbook of the European Convention on Human Rights XII (1969), Chapter IV, Section A(2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ireland v. United Kingdom. Commission Report of 25 January 1976, Decisions and Reports 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ireland v. United Kingdom, judgment of 18 January 1978, Series A, no. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iwanczuk v. Poland, no. 25196/94, 15 November 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalashnikov v. Russia, no. 47095/99, ECHR 2002-VI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keenan v. United Kingdom, no. 27229/95, ECHR 2001-III.

    Google Scholar 

  • López Ostra v. Spain, judgment of 09 December 1994, Series A, no. 303-C.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nevmerzhitsky v. Ukraine, no. 54825/00, 05 April 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peers v. Greece, no. 28525/95, ECHR 2001-III.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raninen v. Finland, no. 20972/92, Commission Report of 24 October 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raninen v. Finland, no. 20972/92, 16 December 1997, Reports 1997-VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith and Grady v. United Kingdom, no. 33985/96; 33986/96, ECHR 1999-VI.

    Google Scholar 

  • T. v. United Kingdom, no. 24724/94, 16 December 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyrer v. United Kingdom, judgment of 25 April 1978, Series A, no. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valasinas v. Lithuania, no. 44558/98, ECHR 2001-VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yankov v. Bulgaria, no. 39084/97, 11 December 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allport, Gordon W. 1937. Personality: A psychological interpretation. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 1969. Four essays on liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cane, Peter. 2002. Responsibility in law and morality. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. Anthony. 2005. Punishment, dignity and degradation. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 25(1): 141–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Gerald. 1988. The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking rights seriously. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 2003. The secular papacy. In Judges in contemporary democracy: An international conversation, eds. Robert Badinter and Stephen G. Breyer, 67–111. New York, NY: NYU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 2006. Justice in robes. Cambridge: The Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Malcolm and Rod Morgan. 1998. Preventing torture: A study of the European convention for the prevention of torture and inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jayawickrama, Nihal. 2002. The judicial application of human rights law: National, regional and international jurisprudence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, Anna and Amrita Mukherjee. 2004. Slopping out in Scotland: The limits of degradation and respect. European Human Rights Law Review 6: 645–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai. 1996. The decent society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCrudden, Christopher. 2008. Human dignity and judicial interpretation of human rights. In European Journal of International Law 19(4): 655–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, William Ian. 1993. Humiliation – And other essays on honor, social discomfort and violence. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millns, Susan. 2002. Death, dignity and discrimination: The case of Pretty v. United Kingdom. German Law Journal 3(10). http://www.germanlawjournal.com/article.php?id=197. Accessed 19 May 2009.

  • Nowak, Manfred. 2005. U.N. Covenant on Civil and Political Rights – CCPR Commentary, 2nd edition. Kehl: NP Engel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 2004. Hiding from humanity: Disgust, shame and the law. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silver, Maury et al. 1986. Humiliation: Feeling, social control and construction of identity. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 16(3): 269–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 1995. On humiliation. Michigan Law Review 93(6): 1787–1804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 2007. Dignity and rank. European Journal of Sociology 48(2): 201–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 2008. Cruel, inhuman and degrading treatment: The words themselves. New York University public law and legal theory research paper series. Working paper 08-36. http://ssrn.com/abstract=1278604. Accessed 15 May 2009.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elaine Webster .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Webster, E. (2011). Degradation: A Human Rights Law Perspective. In: Kaufmann, P., Kuch, H., Neuhaeuser, C., Webster, E. (eds) Humiliation, Degradation, Dehumanization. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 24. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9661-6_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics