Skip to main content

Coherence and Systematization in Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Legal Reasoning and Argumentation

Abstract

This chapter examines coherentist approaches to the justification of normative judgments in law. First, it provides a survey of the main approaches to normative coherence defended in the literature on legal coherentism and discusses the principal objections that threaten to undermine the coherence theory of legal justification. One problem with coherentism, namely the problem of the coherence bias, has not, however, received enough attention in the literature. This chapter states this problem in detail and argues that a modified version of legal coherentism—namely virtue coherentism—has the resources to address this problem. The chapter then engages in a second-order debate about the relevance of coherence in justification by inquiring into the reasons why coherence is worth pursuing when reasoning in law. Finally, this chapter concludes by assessing the value and limits of coherentist reasoning in the legal domain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 299.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, among others, Dworkin (1986), MacCormick (1984, 2005), Alexy and Peczenik (1990), Peczenik (2009), Peczenik and Hage (2004), Günther (1989, 1993), Wintgens (1993, 2000), Hage (2004, 2013). For some earlier coherence theories of legal justification, see Sartorious (1968, 1971), and Hoffmaster (1980).

  2. 2.

    A summary of the main coherence theories across a number of domains is provided in Amaya (2015, Chaps. 3 through 9).

  3. 3.

    For analyses of coherence from a systemic perspective, see Alonso (2006), Pastore (1991), Pérez-Bermejo (2006, 2007), Ratti (2007), and Schröter (2006). On the distinction between systemic and argumentative coherence, see Moral (2003) and Bertea ‘The Argument from Coherence,’ IVR Encyclopaedia of Jurisprudence, Legal Theory and Philosophy of Law, available at http://www.ive-enc.

  4. 4.

    A discussion of evidential reasoning in law is provided by Di Bello and Verheji, Chap. 1, part III, this volume, on ‘Evidential Reasoning.’

  5. 5.

    The difference is not a sharp one, as principles and analogies are very much related; there is, nonetheless, a difference in emphasis that is worth noting and that makes this classification useful.

  6. 6.

    See Bench-Capon and Sartor (2001b), Joseph and Prakken (2009), Amaya (2011, 2015), Araszkiewicz (2010, 2012, 2013), Araszkiewicz and Sãvelka (2012), and Sãvelka (2013).

  7. 7.

    There is another objection that has been raised in the coherentist literature but that I shall not deal with here, to wit, ‘the retroactivity objection.’ The objection is that coherence theories are path-dependent and that this leads to retroactive application of the law. See Kress 1984, 377–388. For responses to Kress’s retroactivity objection, see Hurley (1990, 235–251) and Habermas (1996, 219–220).

  8. 8.

    This contrasts with case-based approaches to coherence, which reduce normative coherence to analogical one.

  9. 9.

    For a discussion of formal approaches to coherence that use belief revision formalisms, see Amaya (2007); for formal approaches to normative coherence within the field of A.I., see Bench-Capon and Sartor (2001a, b, 2003), Hage (2001), Joseph and Prakken (2009); for probabilistic analyses of coherence, see Shogenji (1999) and Olsson (2002, 2005).

  10. 10.

    The label ‘context of pursuit’ is Laudan’s (1977, 110). On this context, see Sintonen and Kikeri (2004, 214–218).

  11. 11.

    Dworkin’s reply to the so-called objection from ‘theory-dependence,’ an objection which, at bottom, is a version of the problem of circularity, also appeals to the relevance of complexity. On the relation between the objection from circularity and the objection from theory-dependence, see Marmor (1991, 79). For a statement of the objection from theory-dependence, see Dworkin (1985, 169). For Dworkin’s response, see Dworkin (1983b, 293).

  12. 12.

    For a presentation of the isolation objection, see Pollock (1974, 27–28). Pollock replies to this very same objection in Pollock (1986, 76–77).

  13. 13.

    See Raz (1985, esp. 305–310). For a discussion of Raz’s critique, see Michelon (2011) and Rodriguez-Blanco (2001).

  14. 14.

    Arguably, this is the kind of response that is suggested by Hage and Pecenick (2004, 337), Hage (2004, 97–99), and Dworkin (1983b, 312).

  15. 15.

    For a statement of this objection, see Williams (1980, 249).

  16. 16.

    Raz (1986, 111). Raz’s critique is directed specifically against Dworkin’s theory of coherence. See also Wacks (1984).

  17. 17.

    The line of response I suggest is thus not available to weak coherence theories insofar as these theories take coherence with the settled law to be a necessary condition of justification.

  18. 18.

    For statements of this objection, see Kress (1996, 538–539) and Raz (1992, 299 and 309 n. 64). Some authors have given yet other reasons why coherence theories undermine the determinacy of law. See Edmunson (1996) and Mackie (1983, 168–169).

  19. 19.

    In a similar vein, Alexy (1998, 46–48) claims that a coherence approach is based on a non-skeptical view about the possibility of weighing values and on some kind of commensurability among values.

  20. 20.

    See Finnis (1987, 374–375), Mackie (1983, 165), and Raz (1992, 309 and 312), for critiques of Dworkin’s coherence theory on the grounds that it assumes value commensurability.

  21. 21.

    In fact, Dworkin seems to be well aware of this problem. See Dworkin (1993, 144, and 1986, 245).

  22. 22.

    The phrase is Plantinga’s. See Plantinga (1993, 112).

  23. 23.

    The point is persuasively argued for by Schauer (1986–1987, 858).

  24. 24.

    This is the problem of authority, which I have discussed above.

  25. 25.

    This objection has also been raised by Critical Legal Studies, specifically against Dworkin’s version of the coherence theory. See Kennedy (1997). For a discussion of the critique advanced by Critical Legal Studies, see Waldron (2008).

  26. 26.

    See Kress (1996, 539–546), for an analysis of the different ways in which coherence and unity relate to each other in various conceptions of coherence. Most versions of the coherence theory in law do not define coherence as unity. A notable exception is Weinrib’s theory. See Weinrib (1988, 1994). For a critique, see Kress (1994).

  27. 27.

    For an extremely illuminating account of the relationship between coherence and conflict in moral deliberation, see Hurley (1989), part III, to whom this response to Raz’s critique owes much.

  28. 28.

    It is crucial to note that by ‘realism’ about truth, I am referring to any theory of truth that claims that truth-makers are mind-independent facts. This is a kind of ‘metaphysical’ realism, importantly distinguished from ‘legal’ realism, as a theory of legal decision-making. In fact, legal realists typically reject realism about truth (at least in the normative domain).

  29. 29.

    See Moore (1985, 2004). See also Brink ( 1989), for a defense of a realist cum coherentist moral epistemology. See BonJour (1985), Lehrer (2000), and Thagard (2000), who defend a coherentist theory of epistemic justification and realism about the truth of empirical beliefs.

  30. 30.

    For an analysis of the problems that arise from combining a coherence theory of legal justification with a realist view about legal facts, see Coleman and Leiter (1993, 612–616).

  31. 31.

    For a defense of a relativist coherentist theory of the truth of moral judgments, see Goldman (1988). See also Young (2001), for a defense of a coherence theory of truth according to which truth amounts to coherence with the largest consistent set of propositions currently believed.

  32. 32.

    There are also important theories about the truth of empirical statements that define truth as coherence by resorting to some idealized perspective. See Putnam (1981) (defining truth as coherence with the system of beliefs that we would hold at the limit of inquiry) and Rescher (1985) (defining truth in terms of ideal coherence, i.e., coherence with a perfected database).

  33. 33.

    This view was defended by Coleman and Leiter (1993: 633–635). Coleman (2001: 165) later rejected this interpretation.

  34. 34.

    This problem is closely related to the ‘problem of access,’ as Coleman and Leiter (1993, 629) term it. The problem of access is as follows. If, according to views of legal truth as ‘ideal’ justification, true propositions about the law are those that one would justifiably hold under ideal conditions, and given that ideal conditions do not obtain (by definition), then it follows that legal truth would be inaccessible to real judges operating in less-than-ideal conditions. Such a theory fails to guide judges in their decision-making task, for it makes legal justification and legal truth unattainable by real judges.

  35. 35.

    I have argued for this view in Amaya (2015, 49–50 and 69).

  36. 36.

    On the confirmation bias, see Mercier and Sperber (2011, 63–66).

  37. 37.

    This is the so-called ‘objection from the bad lot’ or ‘problem of underconsideration’ raised by Van Fraassen against models of inference to the best explanation in science. See Bas Van Fraassen (1989, 142–150).

  38. 38.

    For attempts to impose similar responsibility constraints on justification, see Baehr’s account of evidentialism (2008, 484–485), BonJour’s account of a priori justification (1998, 110–115), and Khalifa’s defense of inference to the best explanation (2010).

  39. 39.

    It critical to note that the responsibilist account of legal justification proposed here is ‘counterfactual’ rather than ‘causal.’ A causal version would say that a legal decision is justified if and only if it is the outcome of epistemically responsible coherence-based reasoning. In contrast, the counterfactual version states that a decision is justified if and only if it could be the outcome of epistemically responsible coherence-based reasoning. Thus, the counterfactual version allows for the possibility that a legal decision be justified, provided that an epistemically responsible legal decision-maker could have accepted it as justified, even if it results from an epistemically irresponsible process of coherence maximization.

  40. 40.

    The most influential contemporary statement of such a view is by Chisholm (1977). For an account of epistemological duties, see Feldman (1988, 2002).

  41. 41.

    The most influential statements of ‘virtue responsibilism’ include Montmarquet (1993) and Code (1987). For a discussion of this trend in virtue epistemology, see Greco (2002).

  42. 42.

    For a lucid discussion of some advantages of virtue theories in both epistemology and ethics, see Zagzebski (1996, 15–29).

  43. 43.

    Alternatively, one could endorse an irenic approach to the standards of epistemic responsibility, which combines deontic and aretaic elements. I have defended such a view before (Amaya 2011). Or one could also make virtues derivative of duties. One way this could be done is by appealing to a duty to ‘behave in ways that will maximize the person’s number of true beliefs and minimize that person’s number of false beliefs’ (Feldman 2002, 372), where these behaviors would include the cultivation and exercise of intellectual virtues.

  44. 44.

    The acceptance of a virtue framework does not, however, imply that deontic notions are irrelevant for determining whether a legal decision-maker has behaved in an epistemically responsible way. A virtue account of the epistemic responsibility of legal decision-makers is compatible with assigning to notions of duty important roles within the theory (Amaya 2015, 523–524).

  45. 45.

    Cf. Simon and Scurich (2011), showing that judicial decisions accompanied by monolithic reasoning—multiple one-sided reasoning—are judged as less acceptable than decisions accompanied by multiple two-sided reasoning. It is unclear, however, whether Simon and Scurich’s results cast doubt over the persuasive value of coherence. As argued, coherence reasoning—and theorizing—rather than explaining conflict away, provides a way to proceed in the way of conflict. Thus, coherence reasoning need not be monolithic, but it is compatible with admitting to good reasons on both sides.

  46. 46.

    That coherence has a constitutive value in individual identity has been argued by Richardson (1994), Thagard and Millgram (1996), and, most extensively, by Hurley (1989). That coherence plays a constitutive role of political communities is argued in Dworkin (1986). See also Michelon (2011), arguing that the value of coherence may be grounded in a narrative conception of human life.

  47. 47.

    The expression is Bender’s (1989, 1).

  48. 48.

    It is critical to note that a certain dose of ‘incoherence’ is also valuable. This does not detract from the plausibility of coherentism, as the benefits of incoherence may be recognized and accounted for from within a coherentist framework. See Haack (2004), Lariguet (2011), and Amaya (2017).

References

  • Alcoff, L. 1996. New versions of the coherence theory. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alcoff, L. 2001. The case of coherence. In The nature of truth, ed. M. Lynch, 159–183. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. 1998. Coherence and argumentation or de genuine twin criterialess super criterion. In On coherence theory in law, ed. A. Aarnio, et al., 41–49. Lund: Juristförlager i Lund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R., and A. Peczenik. 1990. The concept of coherence and its significance for discursive rationality. Ratio Juris 3: 130–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alonso, J.P. 2006. Interpretación de las normas y derecho penal. Buenos Aires: Editores del Puerto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, A. 2015. The tapestry of reason: An inquiry into the nature of coherence and its role in legal argument. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, A. 2007. Formal models of coherence and legal epistemology. Artificial Intelligence and Law 15: 429–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, A. 2011. Legal justification by optimal coherence. Ratio Juris 24: 304–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, A. 2017. The tapestry of reason. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angere, S. 2007. The defeasible nature of coherentist justification. Synthese 157: 321–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angere, S. 2008. Coherence as heuristic. Mind 117: 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Araszkiewicz, M. 2010. Balancing of legal principles and constraint satisfaction. In Legal knowledge and information systems, ed. R.G.F. Winkels. Amsterdam: IOS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Araszkiewicz, M. 2012. Coherence-based account of the doctrine of consistent interpretation. In AI approaches to the complexity of legal systems, ed. M. Palmirani, et al. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Araszkiewicz, M., and J. Savelka. 2012. Two methods for representing judicial reasoning in the framework of coherence as constraint satisfaction. In Legal knowledge and information systems. JURIX: The twenty-fourth annual conference, ed. K. Atkinson. Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Araszkiewicz, M. 2013. Limits of constraint satisfaction theory of coherence as a theory of (legal) reasoning. In Coherence: Insights from philosophy, jurisprudence, and artificial intelligence, ed. M. Araszkiewicz, and J. Šavelka, 217–243. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Atienza, M. 2006. Derecho como argumentación. Barcelona: Ariel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. 1988. Foundationalism, coherentism, and epistemological dogmatism. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 407–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. 1993. The structure of justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, J. 2008. Four varieties of character-based virtue epistemology. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 46: 469–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, J. 2009. Evidentialism, vice, and virtue. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXVIII: 545–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bench-Capon, T., and G. Sartor. 2001a. Theory based explanation of case law domains. In Artificial intelligence, proceedings of the eighth international conference on artificial intelligence and law. New York: ACM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bench-Capon, T., and G. Sartor. 2001b. A quantitative approach to theory coherence. In Legal knowledge and information systems. JURIX 2001: The fourteenth annual conference, ed. B. Verheij et al. Amsterdam: IOS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bench-Capon, T., and G. Sartor. 2003. A model of legal reasoning with cases incorporating theories and values. Artificial Intelligence 150: 97–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bender, J. 1989. Coherence, justification, and knowledge: The current debate. In The current state of the coherence theory: Critical essays on the epistemic theories of Keith Lehrer and Laurence BonJour, with replies, ed. J. Bender, 1–14. Dordrecht, Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. 1985. The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. 1998. In defense of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M.E. 1987. Intention, plans, and practical reasoning. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. 1989. Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R.M. 1977. Theory of knowledge, 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. 1987. Epistemic responsibility. Hanover: University Press of New England.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J. 2001. The practice of principle. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J., and B. Leiter. 1993. Determinacy, objectivity and authority. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142: 549–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, N. 1994. Understanding. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 68 Supp: 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 2001. Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • DePaul, M. 1993. Balance and refinement: Beyond coherence methods of moral inquiry. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, F., and L. Moretti. 2005. On coherent sets and the transmission of confirmation. Philosophy of Science 72: 403–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1972. No right answer? In Law, morality and society, ed. P.M.S. Hacker, and J. Raz, 58–84. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1977. Taking rights seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1983a. A reply by Ronald Dworkin. In Ronald Dworkin and contemporary jurisprudence, ed. M. Cohen, 247–300. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1983b. My reply to Stanley Fish (and Walter Benn Michaels): Please don’t talk about objectivity any more. In The politics of interpretation, ed. W.J.T. Mitchell, 287–313. London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1985. A matter of principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s empire. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1993. Natural Law revisited. In Readings in the philosophy of law, ed. J. Arthur, and W.H. Shaw. New Jersey: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1996. Objectivity and truth: You’d better believe it. Philosophy & Public Affairs 25: 87–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edmunson, W.A. 1996. The antinomy of coherence and determinancy. Iowa Law Review 82: 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. 1988. Epistemic obligations. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. 2002. Epistemological duties. In The oxford handbook of epistemology, ed. P. Moser, 362–385. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. 1987. On reason and authority in law’s empire. Law and Philosophy 6: 173–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L.L. 1969. The morality of law, Rev edn. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.H. 1988. Moral knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.H. 1989. Legal reasoning as a model for moral reasoning. Law and Philosophy 8: 131–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.H. 2002. Practical rules: When we need them and when we don’t. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. 2002. Virtues in epistemology. In The Oxford handbook of epistemology, ed. P.K. Moser, 287–316. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Günther, K. 1989. A normative conception of coherence for a discursive theory of legal justication. Ratio Juris 2: 155–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Günther, K. 1993. The sense of appropriateness: Application discourses in morality and law. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. 2000. A founherentist theory of empirical justification. In Epistemology: An antholog, ed. E. Sosa, and J. Kim, 226–237. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. 2004. Coherence, consistency, congruity, cohesiveness & c.: Remain calm! Don’t go overboard! New Literary History 35: 167–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1996. Between facts and norms. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 2001. Formalizing legal coherence. In Proceedings of the 8th international conference on artificial intelligence and law. New York: ACM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 2004. Law and coherence. Ratio Juris 17: 87–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 2013. Three kinds of coherentism. In Coherence: Insights from philosophy, jurisprudence and artificial intelligence, ed. M. Araszkiewicz, and J. Šavelka, 1–33. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C., and A. Peczenik. 2000. Law, morals, and defeasibility. Ratio Juris 13: 305–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S.O. 2006. Coherence in epistemology and belief revision. Philosophical Studies 128: 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1980. Reasoning and explanatory coherence. American Philosophical Quarterly 17: 151–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1986. Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, C. 1995. The notion of coherence in discourse. In Focus and coherence in discourse processing, ed. G. Rickheit, and C. Habel, 190–202. Berlin: DeGruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmaster, B. 1980. A holistic approach to judicial justification. Erkenntnis 15: 159–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S.L. 1989. Natural reasons: Personality and polity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S.L. 1990. Coherence, hypothetical cases and precedent. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 10: 221–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joseph, S., and H. Prakken. 2009. Coherence-driven argumentation to norm consensus. In Proceedings of the 12th international conference on artificial intelligence and law. ACM: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, D. 1997. A critique of adjudication (Fin de siècle). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. 2010. Default privilege and bad lots: Underconsideration and explanatory inference. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 24: 91–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kress, K. 1984. Legal reasoning and coherence theories: Dworkin’s right thesis, retroactivity, and the linear order of decisions. California Law Review 72: 369–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kress, K. 1994. Coherence and formalism. Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 16: 639–682.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kress, K. 1996. Coherence. In A companion to philosophy of law and legal theory, ed. D. Patterson, 521–539. Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kurzban, R., and C.A. Aktipis. 2007. Modularity and the social mind: Are psychologists too selfish? Personality and Social Psychology Review 11: 131–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lariguet, G. 2011. Todo lo que usted quería saber sobre la coherencia y no se atrevió a preguntarle a Amalia Amaya. Discusiones X: 87–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. 1977. Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. 2000. Theory of knowledge, 2nd ed. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. 2004. Inference to the best explanation, 2nd edn. London and New York: Routledge. 1st edn (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W.G. 1988. Judgment and justification. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, D. (ed.). 2001. The nature of truth. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1983. Dworkin as a Pre-Benthamite. In Ronald Dworkin and contemporary jurisprudence, ed. M. Cohen, 182–204. Totowa: Rowman and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1984. Coherence in legal justification. In Theory of legal science, ed. A. Peczenik, L. Lindahl, and B. van Roermund. Dordrecht: Reidel. A revised version was published in Theorie der Normen. Festgabe für Ota Weinberger zum, ed. W. Krawietz et al. 1984. Berlin: Duncker and Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1993. Argumentation and interpretation in law. Ratio Juris 6: 16–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1994. Legal reasoning and legal theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 2005. Rhetoric and the rule of law: A theory of legal reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. 1983. The third theory of the law. In Ronald Dworkin and contemporary jurisprudence, ed. M. Cohen, 172–181. Totowa: Rowman and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. 1991. Coherence, holism, and interpretation: The epistemic foundations of Dworkin’s legal theory. Law and Philosophy 10: 383–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGarry, J. 2013. The possibility and value of coherence. Liverpool Law Review 34: 17–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H. 2012. The social functions of explicit coherence evaluation. Mind & Society 11: 81–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., and D. Sperber. 2011. Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34: 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michelon, C. 2011. Princípios e Coerência na Argumentação Jurídica. In Direito e Interpretação: Racionalidade e Instituições, ed. C. Barbieri, and R.P. Macedo Jr., 261–285. São Paolo: Saraiva.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millgram, E., and P. Thagard. 1996. Deliberative coherence. Synthese 108: 63–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montmarquet, J. 1993. Epistemic virtue and doxastic responsibility. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M. 1985. A natural law theory of interpretation. California Law Review 85: 459–475.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M. 2004. Objectivity in ethics and law. Dartmouth: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moral, L. 2003. A modest notion of coherence in legal reasoning: A model for the European court of justice. Ratio Juris 16: 296–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moretti, L. 2007. Ways in which coherence is confirmation conducive. Synthese 157: 309–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E.J. 1997. A coherence interpretation of semi-revision. Theoria 63: 105–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E.J. 1998. Making beliefs coherent. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 7: 143–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E.J. 2002. What is the problem of coherence and truth? The Journal of Philosophy 99: 246–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E.J. 2005. Against coherence: Truth, probability, and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E.J., and S. Schubert. 2007. Reliability conducive measures of coherence. Synthese 157: 297–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Österman, B. 2001. Is there a general theory of understanding? Acta Philosophica Fennica 69: 43–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pastore, B. 1991. Sistemi Normativi e Coerenza. In Sistemi normativi statici e dinamici, ed. L. Gianformaggio. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 1990. Coherence, truth, and rightness in the law. In Law, interpretation, and reality: Essays in epistemology, hermeneutics, and jurisprudence, ed. P. Nerhot, 265–309. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 1994. Law, morality, coherence and truth. Ratio Juris 7: 146–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 1998. A coherence theory of juristic knowledge. In on coherence theory of law, ed. A. Aarnio, et al. Lund: Juristförlager i Lund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 1999. The passion for reason. In The law in philosophical perspective, ed. L.J. Wintgens, 173–223. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 2000a. Certainty or coherence? In The reasonable as rational? On Legal Argumentation And Justification. Festschrift for Aulis Aarnio, ed. W. Krawietz et al. Berlin: Duncker and Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 2000b. Scientia Iuris—An unsolved philosophical problem. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2: 273–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 2004. Can philosophy help legal doctrine? Ratio Juris 17: 10–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 2009. On law and reason, 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A., and J.C. Hage. 2004. Legal knowledge of what? Ratio Iuris 13: 326–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pérez-Bermejo, J.M. 2006. Coherencia y sistema jurídico. Madrid-Barcelona: Marcial Pons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pérez-Bermejo, J.M. 2007. Alcune osservazioni sul valore della coerenza nei sistemi giuridici. Diritto e Questioni Pubbliche 7: 43–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pino, G. 1998. Coerenza e verità nell’argomentazione giuridica. Alcune riflessioni. Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia del Diritto 1: 84–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. 1993. Warrant: The current debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. 1974. Knowledge and justification. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. 1986. Contemporary theories of knowledge. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. 2002. Simply the best: A case for abduction. In Computational logic, ed. A.C. Kakas, and F. Sadri, 605–625. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1981. Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinowicz, W. 1998. Peczenik’s passionate reason. In On coherence theory of law, ed. A. Aarnio, et al. Lund: Juristsförlaget i Lund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratti, G.B. 2007. La coerentizzazione dei sistemi giuridici. Diritto e Questioni Pubbliche 7: 61–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999. A theory of justice, rev ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1985. Authority, law, and morality. The Monist 68: 295–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1986. Dworkin: A new link in the chain. California Law Review 74: 1103–1119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1992. The relevance of coherence. Boston University Law Review 72: 273–321.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1985. Truth as ideal coherence. Review of Metaphysics 38: 795–806.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, H. 1994. Practical reasoning about final ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Blanco, V. 2001. A revision of the constitutive and epistemic coherence theories in law. Ratio Iuris 14: 212–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorious, R. 1968. The justification of the judicial decision. Ethics 78: 171–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorious, R. 1971. Social policy and judicial legislation. American Philosophical Quarterly 8: 151–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Šavelka, J. 2013. Coherence as constraint satisfaction: Judicial reasoning support mechanism. In Coherence, insights from philosophy, jurisprudence, and artificial intelligence, ed. M. Araszkiewicz, and J. Šavelka, 203–217. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schröter, M.W. 2006. European legal reasoning: A coherence-based approach. ARSP 92: 86–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuaer, F. 1986–87. The jurisprudence of reasons. Michigan Law Review 85: 847–868.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, S. 2011. Coherence reasoning and reliability: A defense of Shogenji’s measure. Synthese 187: 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, S. 2012. Is coherence conducive to reliability? Synthese 187: 607–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, S., and E. Olsson. 2013. Coherence and reliability in judicial reasoning. In Coherence, insights from philosophy, jurisprudence, and artificial intelligence, ed. M. Araszkiewicz, and J. Šavelka, 33–59. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. 1999. Is coherence truth-conducive? Analysis 59: 338–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D. 2004. A third view of the black box: Cognitive coherence in legal decision-making. The University of Chicago Law Review 71: 511–586.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D., and N. Scurich. 2011. Lay judgments of judicial decision making. Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 8: 709–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D., L.B. Pham, Q.A. Le, and K.J. Holyoak. 2001. The emergence of coherence over the course of decision-making. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition 27: 1250–1260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D., D. Stenstrom, and S.J. Read. 2015. The coherence effect: Blending cognition and emotion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 109: 369–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sintonen, M., and M. Kikeri. 2004. Scientific discovery. In Handbook of epistemology, ed. I. Niiniluoto, M. Sintonen, and J. Wolenski, 205–253. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 1989. Explanatory coherence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12: 425–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 1992. Conceptual revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2000. Coherence in thought and action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2006. Hot thought: Mechanisms and applications of emotional cognition. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2007. Coherence, truth, and the development of scientific knowledge. Philosophy of Science 74: 28–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2012. Coherence: The price is right. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 50: 42–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B.C. 1989. Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wacks, R. 1984. Judges and injustice. South African Law Journal 101: 266–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. 2008. Did Dworkin ever answer the crits? In Exploring law’s empire: The jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin, ed. S. Hershovitz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R.C.S. 1989. The coherence theory of truth: Realism, anti-realism, idealism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib, E.J. 1988. Legal formalism: On the immanent rationality of law. Yale Law Journal 97: 949–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinrib, E.J. 1994. The jurisprudence of legal formalism. Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 16: 583–596.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. 1980. Coherence, justification and truth. Review of Metaphysics 34: 243–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. 1985. Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wintgens, L. 1993. Coherence of the law. ARSP 79: 483–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wintgens, L. 2000. On coherence and consistency. In The reasonable as rational? On legal argumentation and justification. Festschrift for Aulis Aarnio, ed. W. Krawietz et al., 539–550. Berlin: Duncker and Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J.O. 2001. A defense of the coherence theory of truth. The Journal of Philosophical Research 26: 89–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. 1996. Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ziff, P. 1984. Coherence. Linguistics and philosophy 7: 31–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amalia Amaya .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature B.V.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Amaya, A. (2018). Coherence and Systematization in Law. In: Bongiovanni, G., Postema, G., Rotolo, A., Sartor, G., Valentini, C., Walton, D. (eds) Handbook of Legal Reasoning and Argumentation. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9452-0_22

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics