Skip to main content

Formal and Empirical Methods in Philosophy of Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Present Situation in the Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective ((PSEP,volume 1))

Abstract

This essay addresses the methodology of philosophy of science and illustrates how formal and empirical methods can be fruitfully combined. Special emphasis is given to the application of experimental methods to confirmation theory and to recent work on the conjunction fallacy, a key topic in the rationality debate arising from research in cognitive psychology. Several other issues can be studied in this way. In the concluding section, a brief outline is provided of three further examples.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Atkinson, D., Peijnenburg, J., and Kuipers, T. (2009), “How to confirm the conjunction of two disconfirmed hypotheses”, Philosophy of Science, 76, pp. 1-21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L. and Hartmann, S. (2003), Bayesian epistemology, Oxford University Press, Oxford (UK).

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C., Loewenstein, G. and Rabin, M. (2003), Advances in Behavioral Economics, Princeton University Press, Princeton (NJ).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950/1962), Logical Foundations of Probability, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G., Crupi, V., and Festa, R. (forthcoming), “The whole truth about Linda: Probability, verisimilitude, and a paradox of conjunction”, in C. Sinigaglia and M. D’Agostino (eds.), Selected papers from the 2007 Conference of the Italian Association for Logic and Philosophy of Science, College Publications, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1999), “Measuring Confirmation”, Journal of Philosophy, 96, pp. 437–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooke, R.M. (1991), Experts in Uncertainty. Opinion and Subjective Probability in Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford (UK).

    Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., Festa, R. and Buttasi, C. (forthcoming), “Towards a grammar of confirmation”, in M. Dorato, M. Rèdei and M. Suárez (eds.), Selected papers from the First Conference of the European Association for the Philosophy of Science, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., Festa, R. and Mastropasqua, T. (2008), “Bayesian confirmation by uncertain evidence: A reply to Huber (2005)”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, pp. 201-211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., Fitelson, B. and Tentori, K. (2008), “Probability, confirmation and the conjunction fallacy”, Thinking and Reasoning, 14, pp. 182-199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., Tentori, K. and Gonzalez, M. (2007), “On Bayesian measures of evidential support: Theoretical and empirical issues”, Philosophy of Science, 74, pp. 229-252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. and Follette, W.C. (2002), “Rethinking probative value of evidence: Base rates, intuitive profiling and the postdiction of behavior”, Law and Human Behavior, 26, pp. 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. and Follette, W.C. (2003), “Towards an empirical approach to evidentiary ruling”, Law and Human Behavior, 27, pp. 661–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. and Meijs, W. (2007), “Measuring coherence”, Synthese, 156, pp. 405-425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1992), Bayes or Bust?, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA). Joyce, J. (1999), The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (UK).

    Google Scholar 

  • Festa, R. (1999). “Bayesian Confirmation”, in M. Galavotti & A. Pagnini (eds.), Experience, Reality, and Scientific Explanation, Dordrecht, Kluwer, pp. 55–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (1999), “The plurality of Bayesian measures of confirmation and the problem of measure sensitivity”, Philosophy of Science, 66, pp. S362–S378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (2001), “A Bayesian account of independent evidence with applications”, Philosophy of Science, 68, pp. S123-40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (forthcoming), “Bayesian confirmation theory and the Wason selection task”, Synthese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I.J. (1950), Probability and the Weighing of Evidence, Griffin, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (MA).

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, A.J.L. and Hahn, U. (forthcoming), “Bayesian rationality in evaluating multiple testimonies: Incorporating the role of coherence”, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, S. and Meijs, W. (forthcoming) “Walter the banker: The conjunction fallacy reconsidered”, Synthese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, S., Martini, C. and Sprenger, J. (2009), “Consensual decision-making among epistemic peers”, Episteme, 6, pp. 110-129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (2004), “A fallacious fallacy?”, Synthese, 140, pp. 25-35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (2006), Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, Open Court, La Salle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2008), “Milne’s argument for the log-ratio measure”, Philosophy of Science, 75, pp. 413-420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (1999), The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (UK).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (2004), “Bayes’s theorem”, in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2004 Edition), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2004/entries/bayes-theorem/.

  • Kaye, D.H. and Koehler, J.J. (2003), “The misquantification of probative value”, Law and Human Behavior, 27, pp. 645–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. (1921), A Treatise on Probability, Macmillan, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. and Nichols, S. (2008), Experimental Philosophy, Oxford University Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagnado, D.A. and Shanks, D.R. (2002), “Probability judgment in hierarchical learning: A conflict between predictiveness and coherence”, Cognition, 83, pp. 81-112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. and Wagner, C. (1981), Rational consensus in science and society: A philosophical and mathematical study, Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1985), “Illusions about uncertainty”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 36, pp. 331-340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (2004), “Jaakko Hintikka”, Synthese, 140, pp. 37-41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T. (2006), “The structure and function of explanations”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, pp. 464-470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manktelow, K.I., and Over, D.E. (1993), Rationality: Psychological and philosophical perspectives, Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, C.R.M. and Mikkelsen, L.A. (2000), “The psychological side of Hempel’s paradox of confirmation”, Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 7, pp. 360-366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milne, P. (1996), “Log[p(h/eb)/p(h/b)] is the one true measure of confirmation”, Philosophy of Science, 63, pp. 21–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mura, A. (2006), “Deductive probability, physical probability and partial entailment”, in M. Alai and G. Tarozzi (eds.), Karl Popper Philosopher of Science, Rubbettino, Soveria Mannelli, pp. 181-202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mura, A. (2008), “Can logical probability be viewed as a measure of degrees of partial entailment?”, Logic & Philosophy of Science, 6, pp. 25-33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, J.D. (2005), “Finding useful questions: On Bayesian diagnosticity, probability, impact and information gain”, Psychological Review, 112, pp. 979-999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickerson, R.S. (1996), “Hempel’s paradox and Wason’s selection task: Logical and psychological puzzles of confirmation”, Thinking and Reasoning, 2, pp. 1-31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M. and Chater, N. (1994), “A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection”, Psychological Review, 101, pp. 608-631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M. and Chater, N. (2003), “Optimal data selection: Revision, review, and reevaluation”, Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 10, pp. 289-318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M. and Chater, N. (2007), Bayesian Rationality: The Probabilistic Approach to Human Reasoning, Oxford University Press, Oxford (UK).

    Google Scholar 

  • Osherson, D.N., Smith, E.E., Wilkie, O., Lopez, A. and Shafir, E. (1990), “Category-based induction”, Psychological Review, 97, pp. 185-200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perales, J.C. and Shanks, D.R. (2003), “Normative and descriptive accounts of the influence of power and contingency on causal judgement”, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 56A, pp. 977-1007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1956), “A theory of evidence”, Philosophy of Science, 25, pp. 83-94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R., Stich, S. and Bishop, M. (2002), “Ending the rationality wars: How to make disputed about human rationality disappear”, in E.Renee (ed.), Common sense, reasoning and rationality, Oxfor University Press, New York, pp. 236-268.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schupbach J. (forthcoming), “Is the conjunction fallacy tied to probabilistic confirmation?”, Synthese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schupbach, J. and Sprenger, J. (2009), “The logic of explanatory power”, Working Paper, Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (forthcoming), “The degree of epistemic justification and the conjunction fallacy, Synthese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shortliffe, E.H. and Buchanan, B.G. (1984), “A model of inexact reasoning in medicine”, in B.G. Buchanan and E.H. Shortliffe (eds.), Rule-Based Expert Systems, Wesley, Reading (MA), pp. 233-262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sides, A., Osherson, D., Bonini, N., and Viale, R. (2002), “On the reality of the conjunction fallacy”, Memory & Cognition, 30, pp. 191-198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2007), “Bayesian confirmation theory and the likelihood principle”, Synthese, 156, pp. 55-77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (1996), Without good reason, Oxford University Press, Oxford (UK).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1990), The fragmentation of reason, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (ed.) (2009), Experimental Philosophy and Philosophy of Science, in Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A, 40 (Special Issue).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenenbaum, J.B. and Griffiths, T.L. (2001), “The rational basis of representativeness”, in J.D. Moore and K. Stenning (eds.), Proceedings of 23rd Annual Conferenceof the Cognitive Science Society, pp. 1036-1041.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tentori, K. and Crupi, V. (2009), “Explaining the conjunction fallacy: Probability vs. confirmation”, Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tentori, K. and Crupi, V. (forthcoming), “How the conjunction fallacy is tied to probabilistic confirmation: Some remarks on Schupbach (2009)”, Synthese.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tentori, K., Bonini, N. and Osherson, D. (2004), “The conjunction fallacy: A misunderstanding about conjunction?”, Cognitive Science, 28, 467-477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tentori, K., Crupi, V., Bonini, N. and Osherson, D. (2007), “Comparison of confirmation measures”, Cognition, 103, pp. 107-119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1983), “Extensional vs. intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment”, in T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, and D. Kahneman (eds.), Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 19-48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. (1966), “Reasoning”, in B. Foss (ed.), New Horizons in Psychology, Penguin, Harmonsworth (UK), pp. 135-151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. (1968), “Reasoning about a rule”, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 20, pp. 273-281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedell, D.H. and Moro, R. (2008), “Testing boundary conditions for the conjunction fallacy: Effects of the response mode, conceptual focus, and problem type”, Cognition, 107, pp. 105-136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Work supported by a grant from the Spanish Department of Science and Innovation (FFI2008-01169/FISO).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vincenzo Crupi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Crupi, V., Hartmann, S. (2010). Formal and Empirical Methods in Philosophy of Science. In: Stadler, F. (eds) The Present Situation in the Philosophy of Science. The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9115-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics