Advertisement

Analysis of Causation in Medicine

  • Barbara MaierEmail author
  • Warren A. Shibles†
Chapter
Part of the International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine book series (LIME, volume 47)

Abstract

Decision-making, especially diagnosis, depends on a theory of causation. In any particular case an unlimited number of models of causation are possible. Cause may be seen as a hypothesis. Cause is an abstract term. Cause is a concept of human understanding. If the patient is to give a report about him/herself, she is likely to construct it according to how she summarizes what has happened in her life, memories, selections, what she thinks to be received. Causes and causation in medicine are to be carefully examined and healthcare workers have to be cautious in ascribing causes too readily in order to avoid circuits and prejudices in diagnosing and treating patients. All causal statements should be regarded as false unless proven otherwise. The critical definitions of causes have an ethical impact on medical thinking and practice, the lack of doing so invalidates it.

Keywords

Cause distal cause proximal cause causation effect association correlation significance stimulus response 

References

  1. 1.
    Hollingsworth, J., and Lasker, E. 2004. The case against differential diagnosis: Daubert, medical causation testimony, and the scientific method. Journal of Health Law 37:85–111.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Gordis, L. 2005. Epidemiology, 3rd edn. Philadelphia, PA: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Montgomery, K. 2006. How doctors think: Clinical judgment and the practice of medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Mitchell, G., and Benichou, J. 2000. In Encyclopedia of Epidemiological Methods. Chichester, NY: John Wiley.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Hill, A.B.. 1965. The environment and disease. Association of causation? Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine 58:295–300.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Salmon, W. 1998. Causality and explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. 4th edn. Text revision (DSM-IV). 2000. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Shibles, W. 1974. Emotion: The method of philosophical therapy. Whitewater, WI: Language Press. See Chapter on DSM II.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Andreasen, N. 2001. Brave new brain. Conquering mental illness in the era of the genome. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Wittgenstein, L. 1958. Philosophical investigations, 3rd edn. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Melden, A. 1969. The conceptual dimension of emotions. In Human action, ed. Mischel, T. New York: Academic.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Hume, D. 1993. In Enquiry concerning human understanding, 2nd edn. Section 4–7, ed. Steinberg, E.; Hume, D. 1978/1888. In Treatise of human nature, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
  13. 13.
    Elwood, J.M. 1988. Causal relationships in medicine: A practical system for critical appraisal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Stapleton, J. 2002. In Causation in law and medicine, eds. Freckelton, I., and Mendelson, D. Hampshire, GB: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Studdert, D. 2005. Defensive medicine among high-risk specialist physicians in a volatile malpractice environment. JAMA 293:2609–2617PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Goldstein, M., and Goldstein, M. 2002. Controversies in food and nutrition. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Mitford, J. 1998. The American way of death revisited. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Shibles, W. 1987. Reformatory blame. Journal of Rational-Emotive Therapy 5:266–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Katerndahl, D. 2005. Is your practice really that predictable? Nonlinearity principles in family medicine? Journal of Family Practice 54:970–977.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Freckelton, I., and Mendelson, D. eds. 2002. Causation in law and medicine. Hampshire, GB: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Hollingsworth, J., and Lasker, E. 2004. The case against differential diagnosis: Daubert, medical causation testimony, and the scientific method. Journal of Health Law 37:85–111. 509 U.S. 579. 1993.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Tamanaha, B. 1997. Realistic socio-legal theory: Pragmatism and a social theory of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Summers, R.S. 1982. Instrumentalism and American legal theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Hope, T., Savulescu, J., and Hendrick, J. 2003. Medical ethics and law: The core curriculum (for medical students). London: Churchill Livingstone/Elsevier.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Hoffman, D. 2005. The medical malpractice insurance crisis again. Hastings Center Report 35:15–19.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. 26.
    communications@acog.org July 16, 2004.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Schneider, St. 2005. The patient from hell: how I worked with my doctors to get the best of modern medicine and how You can too. New York: Da Capo Press.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Hanson, N. 1958/1961. Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Phillips, C. 1995. Logic in medicine, 2nd edn. London: BMJ.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    cf. Honoré, A. 2002. In Causation in law and medicine, eds. Freckelton, I., and Mendelson, D. Hampshire, GB: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Gasking in Taylor, R. 1967. In Causation. Encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edwards, P., vol 2, 56–66. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Lamb, R.M. 2003. Hospital disclosure protection: Results of a national survey. Health Affairs 22:73–83.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. 33.
    Bridgeman, P.W. 1927. The logic of physics. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Moring, G. 2000. CIG to understanding Einstein, 100. Indianapolis, IN: Alpha Books.Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Tavel, M. 2002. Contemporary physics and the limits of knowledge, 214. New Brunswick, New York: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
  36. 36.
    Buetow, S., and Elwyn, G. 2006. Are patients morally responsible for their errors? Journal of Medical Ethics 32:260–262.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. 37.
    Jenicek, M., and Hitchcock, D. 2005. Evidence-based practice: Logic and critical thinking in medicine. Chicago, IL: American Medical Association Press.Google Scholar
  38. 38.
    McKim, V., and Turner, St. eds. 1997. Causality in crisis? Statistical methods and the search for causal knowledge in the social sciences. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Ropeik, D., and Gray, G. 2002. Risk. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Gynecology and ObstetricsParacelsus Medical University SALKSalzburgAustria
  2. 2.University of Wisconsin–WhitewaterWhitewaterUSA

Personalised recommendations