Skip to main content

Questioning Cosmopolitan Justice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Studies in Global Justice ((JUST,volume 6))

Abstract

How does cosmopolitanism fare as an innovative practical philosophy with a claim to be particularly germane to contemporary problems? More particularly, what does the discourse of cosmopolitan justice contribute to the case that cosmopolitanism is sufficiently different to merit our attention as a new approach within political philosophy, and can this contribution survive critical scrutiny? This chapter seeks to answer these questions principally in relation to that school of contemporary cosmopolitanism which operates within a largely Rawlsian framework and seeks to extend the approach to justice deployed by John Rawls within the confines of the nation-state and apply it, as Rawls did not, to global or transnational spheres. I argue that this project has the initial advantage of marking out a potentially distinctive feature of cosmopolitan theory, something which is lacking in many of the more abstract attempts to define cosmopolitanism, but I go on to question whether it is justice (in contrast, for instance, to humanity) that should be the prime moral basis for establishing morally acceptable institutional arrangements that affect the production and distribution of goods on a global basis. I conclude that it is a theoretical and perhaps practical mistake for cosmopolitans to put so much emphasis on what might be called the globalization of justice as distinct from the globalization of morality more generally.

Thanks are due to those who made helpful points to a paper presented to the International Global Ethics Association conference on “Questioning Cosmopolitanism” at Deakin University, Melbourne on 27th June 2008, and, more particularly, to Nigel Dower and Holly Lawford-Smith, from whose insightful comments I benefited greatly

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kleingeld, Pauline and Eric Brown. 2006. Cosmopolitanism. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.standord.edu/entries/cosmopolitanism.

  2. 2.

    Beitz, Charles. R. 1983. Cosmopolitan Ideals and National Sentiment. Journal of Philosophy 80: 591–600.

  3. 3.

    Barry, Brian. 1982. Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective. In Nomos XXIV: Ethics, Economics and Law, eds. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman, 219–252. New York: New York University Press.

  4. 4.

    Heater, Derek. 1996. World Citizenship and Government: Cosmopolitan Ideas in the History of Western Thought. New York: St Martin’s Press.

  5. 5.

    Kant, Immanuel. 1994. Political Writings. ed. Hans Reiss, trans. H.B. Nisbet, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  6. 6.

    Smith, Adam. 1976. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776). Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press.

  7. 7.

    Smith, Adam. 1982. The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759). Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press.

  8. 8.

    Waldron, Jeremy. 2000. What is Cosmopolitan? Journal of Political Philosophy 8/2: 227–243, 228.

  9. 9.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. Justice Without Borders: Cosmopolitanism, Nationalism, and Patriotism. 10. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  10. 10.

    Ibid, 1.

  11. 11.

    Pogge, Thomas. 1992. Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty. Ethics 103/1: 48–75, 48f: “Three elements are shared by all cosmopolitan positions. First individualism: The ultimate units of concern are human beings, or persons – rather than, say, family lines, tribes, or ethnic, cultural, or religious communities, nations, or states. The latter may be units of concern only indirectly, in virtue of their individual members or citizens. Second universality: The status of ultimate unit of concern attaches to every human being equally – not merely to some subset, such as men, aristocrats, Aryans, whites or Muslims. Third generality: This special status has global force. Persons are ultimate units of concern for everyone – not only for their compatriots, fellow religionists, or such, like.” In a more recent essay, these three elements are reduced to one: “The central [normative] idea guiding [a cosmopolitan’s] moral assessments and prescriptions is that of including all human beings as equal”. He then goes on to distinguish different types of cosmopolitanism as understanding and employing this “central idea” in different ways. See Pogge, Thomas. 2007 (1993). Cosmopolitanism. In A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, ed. Robert E. Goodin, Philip Pettit, and Thomas Pogge, 2nd ed, Vol. 1, 312–329, 312. Oxford: Blackwell.

  12. 12.

    See Campbell, Tom. 2004. The Equal Worth Project. In Globalisation and Equality, ed. Keith Horton and Haig Patapan, 23–48. London: Routledge.

  13. 13.

    Consider Jeremy Bentham’s famous dictum: “each to count for one and no more than one”.

  14. 14.

    Thus, a core element in human rights theory is a rejection of discrimination and an affirmation of equal rights.

  15. 15.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. op. cit. 9.

  16. 16.

    As Tan himself sometimes seems to allow: ibid. 6.

  17. 17.

    Ibid. 2-3; Pogge, Thomas. 2007 (1993). op. cit.

  18. 18.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. op. cit. 10.

  19. 19.

    There is a potential issue arising from the highly individualistic position adopted by Pogge and Tan with respect to other “cosmopolitans” who emphasize the idea of a global community as a morally relevant ontological factor. It is curious that anti-collectivism is a defining feature of cosmopolitanism when at least some cosmopolitans would see the idea of global community as central to their approach. I do not pursue this issue here.

  20. 20.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. op. cit. 2.

  21. 21.

    Ibid. 7.

  22. 22.

    Ibid. 15.

  23. 23.

    Pogge, Thomas. 2007 (1993). op. cit. 312–314.

  24. 24.

    Scheffler, Samuel. 2001. Boundaries and Allegiances. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Particularly chapter 7: “Conceptions of Cosmopolitanism” at p. 112: “Cosmopolitanism about justice is opposed to any view that posits principled restrictions on the scope of an adequate conception of justice… . Cosmopolitanism about culture and the self, meanwhile, is opposed to any suggestion that individuals’ well-being or their identity or their capacity for effective human agency normally depends on their membership of a determinate cultural group whose boundaries are reasonably clear and whose cohesion and stability are reasonably secure”. His view about what these two types of cosmopolitanism have in common is “the idea that each individual is a citizen of the world, and owes allegiance, as Martha Nussbaum has put it, ‘to the worldwide community of human beings’”.

  25. 25.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. 12.

  26. 26.

    Miller, David. 2000. Citizenship and National Identity. 174. Cambridge: Polity Press.

  27. 27.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. op. cit. 65.: “Because the duty of assistance has as its goal the meeting of individuals’ basic needs as well as their collective capacity for sustaining decent institutions, I will refer to this duty as a humanitarian duty. Yet Rawls also stresses that this duty of humanitarian assistance is distinct from, and does not entail, a duty of distributive justice.”

  28. 28.

    Rawls, John. 1972. A Theory of Justice. 3. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  29. 29.

    Campbell, Tom. 2001. Justice. 13–15. London, Macmillan Press.

  30. 30.

    Rawls, John. 1972. op. cit. 98–101.

  31. 31.

    My critique of Rawlsian style global justice favors a broader conception of justice that includes the crucial aspect of natural desert (Brock, Gillian. 2004. Global Distributive Justice, Entitlement and Desert. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31: 109–138) and should not be confused with the rejection of the very idea of global justice.

  32. 32.

    Rawls, John. 1999. The Law of Peoples. 114. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  33. 33.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. op.cit. 19.

  34. 34.

    For a more extended treatment of these arguments, see Campbell, Tom. 2007. Poverty as a Violation of Human Rights: Inhumanity or Injustice? In Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor?, ed. Thomas Pogge, 55–74. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  35. 35.

    Tan, Kok-Chor. 2004. 23. op. cit.

  36. 36.

    Ibid. 36.

  37. 37.

    Ibid. 20, 22–24.

  38. 38.

    Campbell, Tom D. 1974. Humanity Before Justice. The British Journal of Political Science. 4: 1–14.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tom Campbell .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Campbell, T. (2010). Questioning Cosmopolitan Justice. In: van Hooft, S., Vandekerckhove, W. (eds) Questioning Cosmopolitanism. Studies in Global Justice, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-8704-1_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics