Skip to main content

Patterns of Objectification

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 114))

Abstract

Mackie holds that the widespread but erroneous belief that many of our actions are “objectively prescribed” is the result of the human “tendency to read our feelings into their objects.” He calls this “objectification.” (One might also call it “projectivism.”) This Chapter examines the role that the thesis of moral objectification plays in Mackie's endeavors to establish moral skepticism. I conclude that his well-known skeptical arguments (from relativity and queerness) leave matters undecided, and that a further supplementary thesis must be established in order to “explain away” those pro-morality intuitions that threaten to nullify the skeptical arguments' force (via an application of a principle of epistemological conservatism). Moral objectification is designed to be that supplementary thesis. However, Mackie's arguments in favor of this thesis are weak.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The disjunctive phrase “projection or objectification” appears on p. 42 of Mackie (1977), and twice on p. 72 of Mackie (1980).

  2. 2.

    Cf. Barry Stroud's discussion of Humean projectivism: “We do not think that the sequence of events on the billiards table – the one ball's striking the others and the second ball's moving – itself has a feeling or impression like the feeling Hume says we humans get when we observe it… . Nor do we think that an act of willful murder itself has a feeling of disgust or disapprobation, any more than we think that a painting on a wall has a sentiment of pleasure or awe” (Stroud 2000, p. 22).

  3. 3.

    For the curious, I will quickly outline the difficulties of providing a general account of minimal objectification (or “projectivism” as I will call it in this footnote, since I will relate it to subjects for which the latter term is more familiar). An adequate general account of projectivism should cover at least the following cases: (1) moral projectivism, (2) causal projectivism, (3) psychopathological projectivism, and (4) color projectivism. In the interests of illustrating the difficulties of achieving a general account, let me sketch, in the most provisional terms, what these four theories might look like. In moral projectivism, something in the world prompts one to feel disapproval (say), which leads one to experience the thing in the world as forbidden. In causal projectivism, a regularity in the world prompts one to have an expectation, which leads one to experience the world as containing a causal relation. I am not confident that I can give a general account of all forms of psychopathological projectivism, but examples are not hard to come by: A person's poor self-image leads her to interpret her parents as being overly critical or demanding. So far we have three mental states that serve as “intermediaries” between the world and one's experience of the world: disapproval, expectation, and a poor self-image. Yet it is hard to come up with an over-arching category for these three that will not end up capturing too much. And in the case of color projectivism, it is challenging even to come up with an analogous intermediary mental state. The idea is (roughly) that one's visual experience of color owes its quality to the nature of one's sensory apparatus rather than to the real nature of objects' surfaces (even though the sensory apparatus is sensitive to real properties of surfaces). It is not obvious what mental activity is supposed to be getting projected in the creation of one's visual color field. (Visual qualia?) My hunch is that color projectivism can be articulated only as a metaphysical (non-minimal) thesis. It is in light of these kinds of complications that I have sidestepped the delicate task of trying to unify this family of stock examples (and others besides) with a general account, though I confess to harboring the hope of yet doing so in the future. Perhaps in the end there is no entirely satisfactory general account of minimal projection in the offing.

  4. 4.

    See Joyce (2009a), where some features of this account (e.g., what might be meant by “objective”) are discussed in more detail.

  5. 5.

    Needless to say, Mackie himself won't buy the response-dependent account of moral properties. He criticizes such views in general terms in his 1980 book (Chapter 5); and in his 1973 book (Chapter 4) he doubts even the existence of dispositional properties. It is also doubtful that Hume's multifarious uses of the projectivist metaphor are supposed to be compatible with realism. Stroud (2000) emphasizes how, in Hume's account, the content of projectivist experience – be it causal connection, beauty, color, or virtue – is something that could not even be intelligibly predicated of items in the world. Immediately following the famous Treatise projectivist image of the mind's “great propensity to spread itself on external objects,” Hume declares that sounds and smells “really exist no where” (Hume 1739–1740, 1.3.14.24/1978, p. 167) – and context makes it reasonable to think that he will say the same of color and necessary connection. I discuss the error theoretic commitments lying behind Hume's views in Joyce (forthcoming).

  6. 6.

    There is precedence for seeing projectivism and realism as compatible in the Humean literature. See Craig (2000) and Sainsbury (1998).

  7. 7.

    Freud, remember, categorized this sort of projection as a kind of delusion – indicating an antirealist construal.

  8. 8.

    I offer some criticisms of this line of argument – and of Michael Huemer's version of it in particular – in Joyce (2009b).

  9. 9.

    Space does not permit an examination of Mackie's arguments for moral objectification found in his 1946 paper. I do not think any of the arguments found there are superior to those problematic ones which I shall discuss.

  10. 10.

    Incidentally, this comment reveals that Mackie believes that so long as there exists some possible world at which the requisite kind of supernatural being is real, then the error in morality is but a contingent matter. In his forceful case for atheism in his 1982 book, Mackie repeatedly declares the existence of God to be “improbable” (pp. 100, 130, 252–253) – not impossible.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. 1958. Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy 33: 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. 1989. Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R. and C. Tappolet. eds. 1998. European review of philosophy 3: Response-dependence. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. 2000. Hume on causality: Projectivist and realist? In The new Hume debate, eds. R. Read and K. Richman, 113–121. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. 1986. Two conceptions of moral realism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 60(suppl.): 167–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. 2005. Ethical intuitionism. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1739–1740. A treatise of human nature, eds. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch, 2nd ed. 1978. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1751. An enquiry concerning the principles of morals, ed. T. L. Beauchamp. 2006. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. 1989. Dispositional theories of value. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 62(suppl.): 139–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. 1992. How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies 68: 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. 1993. Objectivity refigured: Pragmatism without verificationism. In Reality, representation, and projection, eds. J. Haldane and C. Wright, 85–130. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2007. Moral anti-realism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/moral-anti-realism/. Accessed 17 October 2008.

  • Joyce, R. 2009a. Is moral projectivism empirically tractable? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12: 53–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2009b. The skeptick's tale. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78: 213–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. Forthcoming. Expressivism, motivation internalism, and Hume. In Hume, motivation, and virtue, ed. C. Pigden. London: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. 1946. A refutation of morals. Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy 24: 77–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. 1973. Truth, probability and paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. 1980. Hume's moral theory. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. 1982. The miracle of theism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 1991. Realism and response-dependence. Mind 100: 587–626.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruskin, J. 1856. Modern painters, vol. III. Excerpt in Selections from the work of John Ruskin. 1908. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, R. M. 1998. Projections and relations. Monist 81: 133–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayre-McCord, G. 1986. The many moral realisms. Southern Journal of Philosophy 24(suppl.): 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. 2000. “Gilding or staining” the world with “sentiments” and “phantasms.” In The new Hume debate, eds. R. Read and K. Richman, 16–30. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. 1988. Moral values, projections, and secondary qualities. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 62(suppl.): 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Joyce, R. (2010). Patterns of Objectification. In: Joyce, R., Kirchin, S. (eds) A World Without Values. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 114. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3339-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics