Skip to main content

Cheng Yi’s Moral Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Dao Companion to Neo-Confucian Philosophy

Part of the book series: Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ((DCCP,volume 1))

Abstract

Cheng Yi 程頤 (1033–1107), also known as Cheng Yichuan 伊川, and his brother Cheng Hao 程顥 (1032–1085), are often referred to as “the two Chengs” (er Cheng 二程). They are both identified with the group known as the Five Masters of the (Northern) Song period (with the other three being Zhou Dunyi 周敦頤 [1016–1073], Zhang Zai 張載 [1020–1077], and Shao Yong 邵庸 [1011–1077]). To the extent that Neo-Confucian philosophy can be characterized as the learning of li (li xue 理學, normally translated as “principle”), as it is most commonly called in contemporary Chinese scholarship, the two brothers can be properly credited as its founders: it is only in their philosophy that li obtains its central position for the first time. Thus, in comparison with classical Confucian philosophy, Neo-Confucian philosophy has a more fully developed metaphysics. However, moral life is still the central concern for Neo-Confucians as for classical Confucians. The metaphysics they develop is to provide an ontological articulation of classical Confucian values, and so it is essentially a moral metaphysics. Thus, in this essay on Cheng Yi, I focus on his moral philosophy, paying particular attention to such issues as why be moral, whether one can be moral, how to be moral, the possibility of a virtue politics, and moral metaphysics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The question has often been regarded as something absurd and therefore to be safely ignored. Stephen Toulmin, for example, argues that, just like the question “why are all scarlet things red,” it is a tautological question (Toulmin 1964: 162). F.H. Bradley, on the other hand, thinks that it is a self-contradictory question because it asks for self-interested reason to be moral, i.e., to be not self-interested (Bradley 1935: 61–62). However, Kai Nielsen claims that the question makes sense because it really asks “whether it is rational for me to be moral” (Nielsen 1989: 286–287). David Copp also thinks that the question is intelligible as it asks:“does morality override self-interest?” (Copp 1997: 86).

  2. 2.

    For a more detailed discussion of the topic of why one should be moral, as featured in the history of Western philosophy, see Huang (2008c: 321–330).

  3. 3.

    For a more detailed discussion of the issue of weakness of the will in the Western philosophy, see Huang (2008a: 439–444).

  4. 4.

    For example, Pang Wangli argues that “genuine knowledge is from direct experience and originates from the heart/mind, whereas ordinary knowledge is from indirect experience. Genuine knowledge comes from life experience and practice, whereas ordinary knowledge comes from hearsay” (Pang 1992: 152).

  5. 5.

    In his study of Neo-Confucianism, de Bary devotes a whole chapter to this idea in his book, Learning for One’s Self. On his view, zide—which he translates as “getting it by or for oneself”—has two important senses: “One, relatively low-keyed, is that of learning or experiencing some truth for oneself and deriving inner satisfaction therefrom. Here zide has the meaning of‘learned to one’s satisfaction,’ ‘self-contented,’ ‘self-possessed.’ The other sense of the term is freighted with deeper meaning: ‘getting it or find the Way in oneself” (De Bary 1991: 43); and he relates this second sense to the one used in Mencius 4B.14.

  6. 6.

    It is interesting to note that, while in the Western philosophical tradition, body and mind are usually considered as two separate entities, in this Confucian tradition, they are both regarded as ti: one is the small ti and one is the great ti.

  7. 7.

    Thus, although it is wrong for Feng Richang 馮日昌 to claim that “knowledge from hearing and seeing is what Cheng Yi valued most” (Feng 1991: 175–177), as well as for Lu Lianzhang 蘆連章 and Chen Zhongfan 陳鍾凡 to claim that these two types of knowledge are equally important (see Lu 2001: 142 and Chen 1996: 104), there is still a distinction between a person with knowledge of hearing and seeing and one who is without this knowledge, for one’s knowledge of hearing and seeing can be transformed into knowledge of/as virtue. It is in this sense that Qian Mu 錢穆 pointed out that “it is not that we do not need knowledge from hearing and seeing; it is rather that we need the effort of thinking over and above hearing and seeing” (Qian 2001: 68). This, however, does not mean that all knowledge of/as virtue comes from knowledge of hearing and seeing, as Wen Weiyao 溫偉耀 argues (Wen 1996: 158). For a more detailed discussion of the relationship between these two types of knowledge, see Huang (2008a: 449–451).

  8. 8.

    It is in this connection particularly interesting to see the unique interpretation Cheng Yi gives of two controversial passages in the Analects: “People can be made to follow [the way] but cannot be made to know it” (8.9); and “Only the wise above and stupid below cannot be transformed into each other” (17.3). For a detailed discussion of this interpretation in contrast to the common interpretations, see Huang (2008b).

  9. 9.

    For a more detailed discussion of the problem of the Golden Rule as well as its plausible alternative, see Huang (2005b). For a discussion of the alternative in relation to Confucianism in general and to the Cheng brothers in particular, see Huang (2005a).

  10. 10.

    Indeed, the Mohist term for universal love, jian ai 兼愛, is used by Zhang in a different passage:“Nature is the one source of ten thousand things. It is not something that only I have privately. Only great persons can fully realize the dao. Therefore, their establishing [themselves] must be establishing all, their knowing must be knowing all, and their love must be universal love (jian ai 兼愛)” (Zhang 1978: 21).

  11. 11.

    It is important to note that, while Cheng’s emphasis on fen shu makes him a moral particularist, his emphasis on li yi sets him apart from that group, particularly the more radical ones who undermine the significance of moral experience. For example, stressing moral particularity, John McDowell argues that from our moral experiences we can get nothing but “the capacity to get things right occasion by occasion” (McDowell 1998: 94); and Jonathan Dancy maintains that “there is nothing than one brings to the new situation other than a contentless ability to discern what matters where it matters, an ability whose presence in us is explained by our having undergone a successful moral education” (Dancy 1993: 50; emphasis added). For Cheng however, because of li yi, our appropriate love in one situation, for example our love for our parents, can teach us how to love in a different situation, for example our love for our neighbors’ parents, in far more than a contentless way.

  12. 12.

    Here I agree with David Wong that “loving well requires more of a knowing how than a knowing that. It involves being able to yield to the other’s wishes and claims at the right time and in the right way, and being able to refuse these wishes and claims at the right time and in the right way” (Wong 1989: 255–256).

  13. 13.

    This is similar to what Aristotle says: “Those who are not angry at the thing they should be angry at are thought to be fools, and so are those who are not angry in the right way, at the right time, or with the right persons” (Aristotle 1963: 1126a.5–6).

  14. 14.

    This liberal position is based on the time-honored idea that even a band of robbers needs just rules to be effective. For example, in his Republic, Plato says that “utter rascals completely unjust are completely incapable of effective action” (Plato 1963a: 352e). Later, Saint Augustine makes a similar point: “Justice being taken away, then, what are kingdoms but great robberies? For what are robberies themselves, but little kingdoms? The band itself is made up of men; it is ruled by the authority of a prince, it is knit together by the pact of confederacy; the booty is divided by the law agreed upon” (Augustine 1963: IV.4). At the center of the liberal tradition, Immanuel Kant (1965) also claims that “however harsh it must sound, the problem of establishing a state is soluble even for a nation of devils (as long as they are rational)” (cited in Höffe 1992: 142).

  15. 15.

    For example, although Rawls acknowledges that his principles of justice are chosen by people in the original position who are self-interested (Rawls 1999: 12), such liberals as Robert Audi and Edwin Baker argue that such principles will not make all people self-interested: self-interested people are not allowed to go beyond the bounds of the principles, whereas altruistic people can decide to contribute their just shares to others (Baker 1985: 917–920; Audi 1989: 294).

  16. 16.

    So for Cheng, li (propriety) means three different things: external rules, human feelings, and human nature (which is identical to li [principle]). I hold a different view from Wong Wai-ying, according to whom, ultimately li means external rules and therefore has only an auxiliary function in moral development in Cheng’s philosophy (Wong 2003).

  17. 17.

    In their study of the Cheng brothers, Pan Fuen 潘富恩 and Xu Yuqing 徐余慶 also note this: “humanity, rightness, propriety, and wisdom all originate from people’s feelings. They are made systematic by rulers above and then applied to the people” (Pan and Xu 1988: 160).

  18. 18.

    In recent years, some scholars, following Willard Peterson, prefer to interpret and translate li as “coherence” (Ziporyn 2008, Angle 2009). By coherence, Peterson means the “straight-forward sense of ‘the quality or characteristic of sticking together,’ with the connotations varying according to context” (Peterson 1986: 14). I agree with Peterson that this interpretation is flexible enough to accommodate almost all occurrences of li in the writings of Cheng Yi and Zhu Xi. However, this strength perhaps is also its weakness: it is so flexible that it becomes very vague. In particular, it cannot catch the meaning of li as the life-giving activity (sheng 生) that I think is its central meaning, at least in Cheng, and that I will stress in this section.

  19. 19.

    Lu Lianzhang 蘆連章 is wrong to claim that for Cheng, while li is primary, other categories such as tian, xing (nature), xin (heart-mind), and ming (destiny) are secondary (Lu 2001: 116). In contrast, Mou Zongsan 牟宗三 is fundamentally right in pointing out that “the substance, the principle, and the function refer to heavenly creativity… and so change, dao, and divinity are all different names for the tian dao 天道 (heavenly way) itself” (Mou 1990: 2.23).

  20. 20.

    Qian Mu 錢穆 was wrong to claim that there is only wu li 物理 (li of things), but no ren li 人理 (li of humans) in Neo-Confucian philosophy (Qian 1991: 228). In Qian’s distinction between the classical Confucianism of Confucius and Mencius and the Neo-Confucian philosophy of Cheng Yi and Zhu Xi 朱熹, classical Confucians talked about dao, which includes only the dao of heaven and of human, but not the dao of things; Neo-Confucians talked about li which includes only the li of heaven and things but not a specific li for humans.

  21. 21.

    Mou Zongsan proposed an alternative interpretation by distinguishing two different kinds of li: li as the ontological/metaphysical foundation of the universe (as expressed in such claims as “the reason ten thousand things form one body is that they all have this li ”), and li as the natural tendencies of particular things (as expressed in such claim as “ten thousand things all have their own li ”). As the former, there is only one li under heaven; but as the latter, each thing has its own unique li (Mou 1990: 2.81).

  22. 22.

    I disagree with Hon Tze-ki’s distinction between li and qi: “While li is structured and orderly, qi is dynamic and creative. While li provides the universe with a system of operation, qi sets the universe in motion, propelled by the duality of yin and yang. To move unceasingly, the universe requires both the structure of li and the dynamism of qi” (Hon 2003: 44). Cai Fanglu 蔡方鹿 also argues that “on the relationship between li and things, Cheng believes that there first exists li and then there exist things” (Cai 1996: 69–79). In contrast, I think Pang Wanli 龐萬里 is right: Cheng Yi believes that li and qi “cannot exist independently from each other. When there is one there must be the other. Therefore, the order of li, qi, and image is made in terms of their importance and not in terms of their temporal order” (Pang 1992: 95).

  23. 23.

    This interpretation of Cheng’s li as life-giving activity has some similarity with A.C. Graham’s interpretation of it as growth. However, Graham arrives at an interpretation of life-giving activity (sheng) that is not very far from the Christian idea of creation, despite his own claim otherwise. For example, he argues that “the Song philosophers do not conceive the origin of things as ‘creation’ by Someone standing outside the universe, but as ‘breeding’ growth’ (sheng) from Something at the root of the universe… . It is precisely because the production and growth of things is not explained by preceding physical causes that it is necessary for them to postulate an unseen source out of which things are continually manifesting themselves” (Graham 1992: 108–109). Here, Graham assumes that for Cheng, the ten thousand things originate from “Something at the root of the universe,” an “unseen source.” This “Something unseen” simply does not exist for Cheng. For them everything can be seen, what cannot be seen is the life-giving activity, li, which is not a thing.

  24. 24.

    The interpretation I present here differs from the one advanced by Mou Zongsan, who claims that Cheng Yi, unlike his brother Cheng Hao, thinks that li is static (Mou 1990: 1.44 and 2.78). Mou’s view has not only been generally accepted by scholars in Taiwan, many of whom are Mou’s students; it has also become popular among scholars in mainland China. For example, Pang Wanli also argues that the two brothers understood li differently: whereas Cheng Hao understood it from the perspective of change and movement, Cheng Yi understood it from the perspective of the static structure of things. Pang also cites Zhang Dainian, among others, in support of this interpretation (Pang 1992: 59).

Bibliography

  • Analects 1980. In Translation and Annotations of the Analects 論語譯注, by Yang Bojun 楊伯峻. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angle, Stephen C. 2009. Sagehood: The Contemporary Significance of Neo-Confucian Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1963. Ethica Nicomachea. In Works of Aristotle, vol. ix. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 1979. “Weakness of Will and Practical Judgment.” Noüs 13.2: 173–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 1990. “Weakness of Will and Rational Action.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68: 270–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bol, Peter K. 1992. This Culture of Ours: Intellectual Transitions in T’ang and Sung China. Stanford: Stanford University Press. (Chapter 9 is a substantive study of Cheng Yi as a Neo-Confucian.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, F.H. 1935. Ethical Studies. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cai, Fanglu. 蔡方鹿. 1996. C heng Hao and C heng Yi and Chinese Culture 程顥程頤與中國哲學. Guiyang 貴陽: Guizhou renmin chubanshe 貴州人民出版社. (A comprehensive study of the Cheng brothers’ political, metaphysical, moral, hermeneutical, and educational ideas in a cultural and historical context.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, Wing-tsit (Chen Rongjie). 1962. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Carsun. 1963. The Development of Neo-Confucianism, vol.1. New Haven: College and University Press. (A study of Neo-Confucian philosophy by a prominent contemporary Confucian, with a chapter devoted to Cheng Yi)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Rongjie 陳榮捷 (Wing-tsit Chan). 1991. “The Evolution of the Neo-Confucian Concept of Li as Principle” 新儒學“理”之思想之演進. In Xiang Weixin 項維新 and Liu Zengfu 劉增福 (eds.), Essays on Chinese Philosophical Thought: Song and Ming Periods 中國哲學思想論文集: 宋明篇. Taibei 臺北: Shuiniu chubanshe 水牛出版社. (A classic discussion of the various meanings of li in different Neo-Confucian writings)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Zhongfan 陳鐘凡. 1996. Introduction to Song Thought 兩宋思想述評. Beijing 北京:Dongfang chubanshe 東方出版社. (An early study [1940s] of Song thinkers, with a chapter discussing Cheng Yi’s dualism of li and qi.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, Hao 程顥, and Cheng Yi 程頤. 2004. The Works of the Two Chengs 二程集. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局. (Original texts of the Cheng brothers, including Surviving Works [Yishu 遺書], External Works [Waishu 外書], Collected Writings [Wenji 文集], C heng Yi’s Commentary on the Book of Change [Zhouyi Cheng shi zhuan 周易程氏傳], Interpretation of Classics [Jingshuo 經說], and Excellent Sayings [Cuiyan 粹言].)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2002. If You’re an Egalitarian, How Come You’re So Rich? Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, David. 1997. “The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and the Unity of Reason.” Social Philosophy and Policy 14: 86–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, Jonathan. 1993. Moral Reason. Oxford, UK, and Cambridge, US: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1970. “How Is Weakness of Will Possible?” In his Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1982. “Paradoxes of Irrationality.” In Richard Wollheim and James Hopkins (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Bary, Wm. Theordore. 1991. Learning for One’s Self: Essays on the Individual in Neo-Confucian Thought. New York: Columbia University Press. (Ten essays, with a focus on Wang Yangming.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Feng, Richang 馮日昌. 1991. “The Cheng Brothers’s View on The Investigation of Things and The Extension of Knowledge” 二程格物致知論. In Xiang Weixin 項維新 and Liu Zengfu 劉增福 (eds.), Essays on Chinese Philosophical Thought: Song and Ming Periods 中國哲學思想論集: 宋明篇. Taibei 臺北: Shuiniu chubanshe 水牛出版社. (A textual study of the Cheng brothers’ theory of knowledge.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Feng, Youlan 馮友蘭. 1995. A New History of Chinese Philosophy 新編中國哲學史, vol. 5. Beijing 北京: Renmin chubanshe 人民出版社. (Includes a substantive chapter devoted to a combined study of the Cheng brothers.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fung, Yu-lan (Feng Youlan). 1953. A History of Chinese Philosophy. vol. 2. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Half a chapter devoted to the Cheng brothers.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth, Alan. 1980. “The Golden Rule Rationalized.” In Midwest Studies in Philosophy 3: 133–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, A.C. 1992. Two Chinese Philosophers. La Salle, IL: Open Court. (Still the only book-length study of the Cheng brothers in English, with translations of many passages by the Chengs.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1998. Leviathan, edited by J. C. A. Gaskin. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, Otfried. 1992. “‘Even a Nation of Devils Needs the State’: the Dilemma of Natural Justice.” In Howard Lloyd Williams (ed.), Essays on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hon, Tze-ki. 2003. “Cheng Hao” and “Cheng Yi.” In A. S. Cua (ed.), Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy. New York: Routledge. (Two in-depth encyclopedia articles on the two brothers.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hou, Wailu, 侯外蘆 et al. 1997. A History of Philosophy of Li from Song to Ming 宋明理學史. vol.1. Beijing 北京: Renmin chubanshe 人民出版社. (Part of a two-volume set of an intellectual history of Neo-Confucianism, with a long chapter devoted to a combined study of the Cheng brothers.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Siu-chi. 1999. Essentials of Neo-Confucianism: Eight Major Philosophers of the Song and Ming Periods. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press. (One chapter is devoted to a philosophical study of Cheng Yi.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yong. 2005a. “Confucian Love and Global Ethics: How the Cheng Brothers Would Help Respond to Christian Criticisms.” Asian Philosophy 15.1: 35–60. (A discussion of the contemporary significance of the Cheng brothers’ interpretation of love with distinction.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yong. 2005b. “A Copper Rule Versus the Golden Rule: A Daoist-Confucian Proposal for Global Ethics.” Philosophy East and West 55.3: 394–425. (An argument for the moral principle “do (don’t do) unto others as they would (would not) like to be done unto.”)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yong. 2007a. “The Cheng Brothers’s Onto-Theological Articulation of Confucian Values.” Asian Philosophy 17.3: 187–211. (An interpretation of the Cheng brothers’ li 理 as life-giving activity.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yong. 2007b. “Neo-Confucian Political Philosophy: The Cheng Brothers on Li (Propriety) as Political, Psychological, and Metaphysical.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 34.2: 217–239. (An exposition of the Cheng brothers’ li 禮 as rules of action, as inner feeling, and as human nature.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yong. 2008a. “How Is Weakness of the Will Not Possible? Cheng Yi’s Neo-Confucian Conception of Moral Knowledge.” In Roger T. Ames and Peter D. Herschock (eds.), Educations and Their Purposes: A Conversation among Cultures. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. (An attempt to use Cheng Yi’s conception of moral knowledge to shed light on the issue of weakness of the will.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yong. 2008b. “Neo-Confucian Hermeneutics at Work: Cheng Yi’s Philosophical Interpretation of Analects 8.9 and 17.3.” Harvard Theological Review 101.1: 169–201. (An exposition of Cheng’s unique interpretation of these two controversial Analects passages.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yong. 2008c. “Why Be Moral? The Cheng Brothers’ Neo-Confucian Answer.” Journal of Religious Ethics 36.2: 321–353. (A discussion of the Cheng brothers’ conception of human nature as a response to the question of why be moral.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1957. An Inquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. New York: The Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1965. Critique of Practical Reason, translated by Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, Rizhang 李日章. 1986. C heng Hao and C heng Yi 程顥 程頤. Taibei 臺北: Dongda tushu gongsi 東大圖書公司. (An introductory, comprehensive, and combined study of the Cheng brothers)

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Xiangbin 劉象彬. 1987. A Study of the Main Categories of the Cheng Brothers’ Principle-centered Learning 二程理學基本範疇硏究. Kaifeng 開封: Henan daxue chubanshe 河南大學出版社. (A combined study of the Cheng brothers according to their main philosophical categories.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu, Lianzhang 蘆連章. 2001. A Critical Biography of C heng Hao and C heng Yi 程顥程頤評傳. Nanjing 南京: Nanjing daxue chubanshe 南京大學出版社. (A comprehensive combined study of the Cheng brothers’s thought in relation to their life events.)

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1998. “Comments on ‘Some Rational Aspects of Incontinence’ [by T.H. Irvin].” Southern Journal of Philosophy, suppl. 27: 89–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, Allison. 1990. “Is Akratic Action Always Irrational?” In Owen Flanagan and Amelie Rorty (eds.), Identity, Character, and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melden, A.I.1948. “Why Be Moral?” The Journal of Philosophy 45: 449–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mencius. In Contemporary Translation of the Mencius 孟子今譯, translated by Liu Fangyuan 劉方元. Nanchang 南昌: Jiangxi renmin chubanshe 江西人民出版社.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mou, Zongsan 牟宗三. 1990. Onto-cosmological State of the Original Heart/Mind and Human Nature 心體 與性體, 3 vols. Taibei 臺北: Zhengzhong shuju 正中書局. (An authoritative study of Song and Ming Neo-Confucianism, with one third of volume 2 devoted to a study of Cheng Yi.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie. G. 1999. “A Paradox about the Justification of Punishment.” In George Sher and Baruch A. Broady (eds.), Social and Political Philosophy: Contemporary Readings. Orlando, FL: Harcourt Brace College Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, Kai. 1989. Why Be Moral. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okin, Susan Moller. 1989. Justice, Gender, and the Family. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okin, Susan Moller. 2005. “ ‘Forty Acres and a Mule’ for Women.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 4 (2): 233–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pan, Fuen 潘富恩, and Xu Yuqing 徐余慶. 1988. A Study of Cheng Hao and Cheng Yi’s Philosophy 程顥程頤哲學研究. Shanghai 上海: Fudan daxue chubanshe 復旦大學出版社. (The most comprehensive combined study of the Cheng brothers.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Willard. 1986. “Another look at Li.” The Bulletin of Sung and Yuan Studies 18: 13–31. (A classical essay interpreting li as “coherence” and surveying its different meanings.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Pang, Wanli 龐萬里. 1992. The Philosophical System of the Cheng Brothers 二程的哲學體系. Beijing 北京: Beijing hangtian hangkong daxue chubanshe 北京航天航空大學出版社. (A valuable study of the Cheng brothers, focusing on the similarities and differences between the two, with an appendix identifying the authorship of passages in the Yishu which are not otherwise explicitly attributed.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1963a. Protagoras. In Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (eds.), The Collected Dialogues of Plato. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1963b. Republic. In Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (eds.), The Collected Dialogues of Plato. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Qian, Mu 錢穆. 1991. “Confucius-Mencius and Cheng-Zhu 孔孟與程朱.” In Xiang Weixin 項維新 and Liu Zengfu 劉增福 (eds.), Essays on Chinese Philosophical Thought: Song and Ming Periods 中國哲學思想論集: 宋明篇. Taibei 臺北: Shuiniu chubanshe 水牛出版社. (An essay contrasting classical Confucian philosophical thought and Neo-Confucian philosophical thought.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Qian, Mu 錢穆. 2001. An Introduction to Neo-Confucianism 宋明理學概述. Taibei 臺北: Lantai chubanshe 蘭臺出版社. (Chapter 17 is a short introduction to Cheng Yi by a renowned intellectual historian.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, Michael. 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Kidder, Jr., Peter K. Bol, Joseph A. Adler, and Don J. Wyatt. 1990. Sung Dynasty Uses of the I Ching. Princeton: Princeton University. (Chapter Five is a study of Cheng Yi’s interpretation of the Book of Change.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tang, Junyi 唐君毅. 1985. On the Origin of Chinese Philosophy: Introduction 中國哲學原論:導論篇. Taibei 臺北: Xuesheng shuju 學生書局. (A multi-faceted study of Chinese philosophy.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen. 1964. An Examination of the Place of Reason in Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1989. The Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tu, Weiming 杜維明. 1999. “Humanity as Embodied Love: Exploring Filial Piety in a Global Ethical Perspective.” In Marko Zlomislic (ed.), Jen, Agape, Tao with Tu Wei-ming. Binghamton, Global Publications. (A defense of the idea of filial piety by the most prominent contemporary Confucian.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tu, Weiming 杜維明. 2002. (a) “Confucian Anthropology of Body, Heart/Mind, Soul, and Spirit” 從身、心、靈、神四層次看儒家的人學; (b) “Confucius: Reflection on Humanity” 孔子:人的反思; (c)“On Confucian ‘Inner Experience’: Knowledge of/as Virtue” 論儒家的「體知」: 德性之知的含義; (d) “Human Dignity: From the Perspective of the Inner Experience” 從‘體知’看人的尊嚴; (e) “A Contemporary Interpretation of Confucian Tradition of Inner Experience” 儒家‘體知’傳統的現代詮釋. In Collected Works of T u Weiming 杜維明文集, vol. 5. Wuhan 武漢: Wuhan chubanshe 武漢出版社. (A group of articles focused on the idea of tizhi 體知, knowledge from internal experience.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wen, Weiyao 溫偉耀. 1996. The Way to Sagehood: A Study of the Cheng Brothers on Moral Cultivation 成聖之道:北宋二程修養功夫論之研究. Taibei 臺北: Wenshizhe chubanshe 文史哲出版社. (A study of the Cheng brothers with a focus on their view of moral cultivation.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong, Wai-ying 2003. “The Status of Li in the Cheng Brothers’s Philosophy.” Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 3.1: 109–119. (An important study of Cheng brothers’ conception of propriety.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong, David 1989. “Universalism Versus Love with Distinction: An Ancient Debate Revived.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 16: 252–272. (A seminal discussion of the ancient debate between Confucians and Mohists.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Yongjun 張永儁. 1988. A Limited Study of the Two Chengs 二程學管見. Taibei 臺北: Dongda tushi gongsi 東大圖書公司. (A collection of essays on the Cheng brothers, with a focus on the interpretation of their philosophy by their disciples.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Zai 張載. 1978. The Complete Works of Z hang Zai 張載集. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中華書局.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziporyn, Brook. 2008. “Form, Principle, Pattern, or Coherence? Li 理 in Chinese Philosophy.” Philosophy Compass 3.3: 401–422. (A survey article of the various meanings, and various interpretations of these meanings, of li in the history of Chinese philosophy.)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Huang Yong .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Yong, H. (2010). Cheng Yi’s Moral Philosophy. In: Makeham, J. (eds) Dao Companion to Neo-Confucian Philosophy. Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2930-0_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics