Skip to main content

Phenomenology and Cognitive Linguistics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science

Abstract

The purpose of this chapter is to describe some similarities, as well as differences, between theoretical proposals emanating from the tradition of phenomenology and the currently popular approach to language and cognition known as cognitive linguistics (hence CL). This is a rather demanding and potentially controversial topic. For one thing, neither CL nor phenomenology constitute monolithic theories, and are actually rife with internal controversies. This forces me to make certain “schematizations”, since it is impossible to deal with the complexity of these debates in the space here allotted.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “The experimental method is indispensible. /…/ But this does not alter the fact that it presupposes what no experiment can accomplish, namely the analysis of conscious life itself. /…/ Phenomenological psychology is interested primarily in the necessary a priori of every possible empirical psychology” (Kockelmans 1967: 425, 447, quoted by Itkonen 2003: 110). The complementary relationship between phenomenological psychology (Husserl [1925] 1977; Gurwitsch 1964) and phenomenological philosophy, focusing respectively on the ego and world poles of the intentional relation is discussed by Sonesson (2007).

  2. 2.

     However, some modern philosophers of mind, bedeviled with the failures of both physicalist and dualist theories to explain consciousness, appear to be willing to adopt a form of monism which is reminiscent of Husserl’s transcentendal idealism, e.g. Honderich (2006) theory of “radical externalism” or “consciousness as existence”.

  3. 3.

    Some (like an anonymous reviewer) are liable to dispute this claim, and point out that Lakoff and Johnson (1999) postulate different “levels of embodiment” (cf. Section on Embodiment), while Rohrer (2007a,b) explicitly argues that his “levels of investigation” framework in not reductionist: “research in embodied cognitive science should not seek to reduce such phenomena to another level but should instead bridge across these levels” (Rohrer 2007a: 346). Lakoff and Johnson (1999) describe their ontological position as being one of “noneliminative physicalism” (ibid: 109), where “each level is taken as real, as having a theoretical ontology necessary to explain phenomena. … explanation and motivation flow in both directions.” (ibid: 113). However, while this may qualify as an epistemological non-reductionism, ontologically Lakoff and Johnson are physicalists, accepting without any argument “the lack of any mind-body gap” (ibid: 96). Also, just considering that 4 of the 6 “levels of investigation” in Rohrer’s “non-reductive” framework deal with increasingly high-grained analysis of the brain (“Neural systems”, “Neuroanatomy”, “Neurocellular systems” and “Subcellular systems”), while the two highest: “Communicative and cultural systems” and “Performance domain” are characterized as “Multiple central nervous systems” and “Central nervous systems” shows what is really real for this strand of cognitive linguistic thinking. A non-reductionist neuroscientific cognitive linguistics is indeed possible, but as in neurophenomenology (Varela 1996), that would mean not privileging the objective, third-person perspective, but rather starting from, and keeping a focus on, the experiences of speakers, while looking for correlations with these in e.g. neuroimaging studies. I am not aware that any CL-researchers have carried out such projects, but they are of course quite possible.

  4. 4.

    And even less the first-person plural “we”, as done by Rohrer (2007b: 35) in paraphrasing the same passage.

  5. 5.

     Though, of course, Husserl would never have accepted the existence of “brute facts”, and rather have said that they belong to another part of the Lifeworld than the institutional ones. A criticism that may be leveled at the early Husserl is that he, similar to Gibson (1979) hardly recognized the existence of the latter (cf. Sonesson 1989).

  6. 6.

    By convention, linguists prefix “ungrammatical sentences”

  7. 7.

     Again, depending on one’s purposes one may need to “go beyond” such description and seek “explanations” in terms of evolution, ontogenetic development, history, neuroscience etc. Hence, there are subfields of linguistics devoted specifically to such investigations in which phenomenology is indeed “never enough”: psycholinguistics, neurolinguistics, diachronic (historical) linguistics etc. The grounds for these, including notions such as “sentence”, “word”, “sense” are, however, set by (informal) phenomenological methods.

  8. 8.

     This is a mistake committed by Katz (1981): “The properties Katz assigns to abstract objects appear all to be possessed by the kind of conventions of mutual knowledge that Esa Itkonen argues are constitutive of linguistic rules (Itkonen 1978; not cited in Katz 1981)” (Pateman 1987: 2).

  9. 9.

     A defense of the reality of “unconscious computation”, suggested by an anonymous reviewer, in line with the view of metaphor expressed by Lakoff and Johnson (1999) is that what is termed “metaphorical” is no less real than what is termed “literal”, as long as it plays an explanatory role. And the level of the “cognitive unconscious” plays such a role, both upwards towards consciousness and downwards with respect to the brain. However, this seems to conflate ontology and epistemology (cf. footnote 3). While both consciousness and the brain are in the broad phenomenological sense empirical phenomena, “unconscious computation” is not, and simply a form of describing either one or the other. But in attempting to capture aspects from both - intentionality on the one hand, and bio-physical causality on the other - it becomes simply incoherent, which is why Searle (1992) argues that we would do best to dispend with it. For a more extensive argument, cf. Zlatev (2007a).

  10. 10.

    In the name of fairness, it should be pointed out that Lakoff, Johnson and Rohrer do not explicitly deny a representational relation between language or pictures and reality, but of “internal representations” of the kind assumed by “first generation” cognitive scientists. However, they never provide an account of “external representations” either, or of internalized such (Vygotsky 1978), and fail to draw a distinction between sensory-motor and representational processes (cf. Ikegami and Zlatev 2007), due to their insistence on a strong form of “evolutionary continuity”.

  11. 11.

    Sonesson (1989) has, however, shown that this picture needs to be complicated a bit. Bildobjekt cannot be the mediating content, since the latter involves a sort of “quasi-perception” in the words of Husserl, e.g. in perceiving a black and white photo, the skin of a given person is seen as white, or grey, while I know that the actual Sujet (referent) has a certain color. Hence, Sonesson adds another mediating “layer”, corresponding to, in the example given, to the apple, as I know that it is: colorful, round etc, that would continue to exist even if the last apple on Earth were eaten.

  12. 12.

     The unacknowledged parallels between Gurwitsch and Langacker are further explored by Sonesson (2004).

References

  • Cassirer E (1957) The philosophy of symbolic forms. III. The phenomenology of knowledge. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1975) Reflections on language. Pantheon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997) Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Clausner T, Croft W (1999) Domains and image schemas. Cogn Linguist 10:1–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen JL (1986) The dialoge of reason: an analysis of analytical philosophy. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Costall A (2007) Bringing the body back to life: James Gibson’s ecology of embodied agency. In: Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank R. (eds) Body, language and mind. Embodiment Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin 1:55–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Croft W (2007) The origins of grammar in the verbalization of experience. Cogn Linguist 18(3):339–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio A (2000) The feeling of what happens. body, emotion and the making of consciousness. Harvester, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1987) The intentional stance. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Depraz N (2001) The Husserlian theory of intersubjectivity as alterology. J Conscious Stud 8(5–7):169–178

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewell R (2005) Dynamic patterns of CONTAINMENT. In: Hampe, B (ed) From perception to meaning. Image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 369–394

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J (1981 [1925]) John Dewey, The later works, 1925–1953, vol 1. Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodge E, Lakoff G (2005) Image schemas: from linguistic analysis to neural grounding. In: Hampe B (ed) From perception to meaning: image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 57–91

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (1982) Semiotics and the philosophy of language. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman G (1992) Bright air, brilliant fire: on the matter of the mind. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans V (2003) The structure of time. language, meaning and temporal cognition. Benjamins, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Fauconnier G, Turner M (2002) The way we think: conceptual blending and the mind’s hidden complexities. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1966 [1892]) On sense and referece. In: Geach P, Black M (eds) Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2005) How the body shapes the mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Broested-Soerensen J (2006) Experimenting with phenomenology. Conscious Cogn 15:119–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Hutto DD (2008) Understadning others through primary interactions and narrative practice. In: Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 17–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V, Lakoff G (2005) The brain’s concepts: the role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cogn Neuropsychol 22(3/4):455–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner H (1987) The mind’s new science. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Geeraert D, Cuyckens H (eds) (2007a) The Oxford handbook of cognitive linguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Geeraerts D, Cuyckens H (2007b) Introducing cognitive linguistics. In: Geeraerts D, Cuyckens H (eds) The Oxford handbook of cognitive linguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 3–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs R (2005) The psychological status of image schemas. In: Hampe B (ed) From perception to meaning: image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 113–135

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J (1979) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Grady JE (2005) Image schemas and perception: refining the definition. In: Hampe B (ed) From perception to meaning: image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 35–56

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch A (1964) The field of consciousness. Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampe B (ed) (2005) From perception to meaning: image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Harder P (2007) Cognitive linguistics and philosophy. In: Geeraerts D, Cuyckens H (eds) The Oxford handbook in cognitive linguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1241–1265

    Google Scholar 

  • Haser V (2005) Metaphor, metonymy and experientialist philosophy. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Heine B, Kuteva T (2002) On the evolution of grammatical forms. In: Wray A (ed) The transition to language. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 376–397

    Google Scholar 

  • Honderich T (2006) Radical externalism. Journal of Consciousness Studies 13(7–8):3–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1970 [1936]) The crisis of European sciences and transcentental phenomenology. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1977 [1925]) Phenomenological psychology. Nijhoff, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1989 [1952]) Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, second book. Klewer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (2001 [1900]) Logical investigations. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto D (2008) First communions: mimetic sharing without theory of mind. In: Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 245–276

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikegami T, Zlatev J (2007) From pre-representational cognition to language. In: Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank R (eds) Body, language and mind, vol 1. Embodiment. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 197–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Itkonen E (1978) Grammatical theory and metascience: a critical inquiry into the philosophical and methodological foundations of “autonomous” linguistics. Benjamins, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Itkonen E (2003) What is language? a study in the philosophy of linguistics. Turku University Press, Turku

    Google Scholar 

  • Itkonen E (2005) Analogy as structure and process: approaches in linguistics, cognitive psychology and the philosophy of science. Benjamins, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Itkonen E (2008) The central role of normativity for language and linguistics. In: Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha E, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 279–306

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson M (1987) The body in the mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson M (2005) The philosophical significance of image schemas. In: Hampe B (ed) From perception to meaning: image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 15–34

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson M, Lakoff G (2002) Why cognitive linguistics requires embodied realism. Cognitive Linguistics 13(3): 245–263

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson M, Rohrer T (2007) We are live creatures: Embodiment, American pragmatism and the cognitive organism. In: Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank R (eds.) Body, language and mind. Embodiment. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin 1:17–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz J (1981) Language and other abstract objects. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans JJ (1967) Phenomenology: the philosophy of Edmund Husserl and its interpretation. Doubleday, Garden City, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G, Johnson M (1980) Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G (1987) Women, fire and dangerous things: what categories reveal about the mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G (1988) Cognitive semantics. In: Eco U, Santambrogio M, Violi P (eds) Meaning and mental representations. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, pp 119–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G, Johnson M (1999) Philosophy in the flesh: the embodied mind and its challange to western thought. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker R (1986) Abstract motion. Proc Annu Meet Berkeley Linguist Soc 12:455–471

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker R (1987) Foundations of cognitive grammar, vol 1. Stanford University Press, Standord

    Google Scholar 

  • Langacker R (2006) Subjectification, grammaticaliztion, and conceptual archetypes. In: Athanasiadou A, Canakis C, Cornillie B (eds) Subjectification: various paths to subjectivity. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 17–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotman J, Uspenskij B, Ivanov V, Toporov V, Pjatigorski A (1975) Thesis on the semiotic study of cultures (as applied to slavic texts). In: Sebeok T (ed) The tell-tale sign: A survey of semiotics. Peter de Ridder, Lisse, pp 57–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler J (1991) Prelinguistic primitives. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 17:414–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandler J (2004) The foundations of mind: origins of conceptual thought. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff A, Moore MK (1983) Newborn infants imitate adult facial gestures. Child Dev 54:702–709

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1962 [1945]) Phenomenology of perception. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague R (1974) Formal philosophy: selected papers of richard montague. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran D (2005) Husserl: founder of phenomenology. Polity, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nerlich B, Clarke DD (2007) Cognitive linguistics and the history of linguistics. In: Geeraerts D, Cuyckens H (eds) The Oxford handbook in cognitive linguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 599–607

    Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard M (2004) On the naturalizing of phenomenology. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 3(4):365–379

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pateman T (1987) Language in mind and language in society. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J (1945) La formation du symbole chez l’enfant. Delachaux et Niestlé

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (1994) The language instinct. William Morrow, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Popova Y (2005) Image schemas and verbal synaesthesia. In: Hampe B (ed) From perception to meaning: image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 395–419

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1981) Reason, truth and history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Regier T (1996) The human semantic potential. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohrer T (2007a) The body in space: Dimensions of embodiment. In: Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank R (eds) Body, language and mind. Embodiment. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin 1:339–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohrer T (2007b) Embodiment and experientialism. In: Geeraert D, Cuyckens H (eds). The Oxford handbook of cognitive linguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 25–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Saeed JI (2003) Semantics, 2nd edn. Blackwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre J-P (1956 [1943]) Being and nothingness. a phenomenological essay on ontology. Washington Square, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Saury J-M (2004) The phenomenology of negation and its expression in natural language. Göteborg University, Department of Linguistics, Göteborg

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1983) Intentionality, an essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1995) The construction of social realiy. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1992) The rediscovery of the mind. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (2002) Consciusness and language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2004) Preserving integrity against colonization. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3(3):249–261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinha C (1999) Grounding, mapping and acts of meaning. In: Janssen T, Redeker G (eds) Cognitive linguistics: foundations, scope and methdology. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 223–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinha C, Rodríguez C (2008) Language and the signifying object: from convention to imagination. In: Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, pp 357–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Sonesson G (1989) Pictorial concepts. inquiries into the semiotic heritage and its relevance for the analysis of the visual world. Aris/Lund University Press, Lund

    Google Scholar 

  • Sonesson G (2004) Perspective from a semiotical perspective. In: Rossholm G (ed) Essays on fiction and perspective, Peter Lang, Bern, pp 255–292

    Google Scholar 

  • Sonesson G (2006) The meaning of meaning in biology and cognitive science. Sign Syst Stud 34(1):135–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Sonesson G (2007) From the meaning of embodiment to the embodiment of meaning: a study in phenomenological semiotics. In: Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank R (eds) Body, language and mind, vol 1: Embodiment. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 85–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern DN (2000 [1985]).The interpersonal world of the infant: a view from psychoanalysis and developmental psychology. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy L (2000) Toward a cognitive semantics, vols 1 and 2. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson AL (2002) Instrospection and phenomenological method. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 2(3):239–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E (2001) Empathy and consciousness. J Conscious Stud 8(5–7):1–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Traugott E (1989) On the rise of epistemic meanings in English: an example of subjectification in semantic change. Language 65:ss. 31–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen C (1979) Communication and cooperation in early infancy: a description of primary intersubjectivity. In: Bullowa M (ed) Before speech. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 321–347

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner M (2007) Conceptual integration. In: Geeraerts D, Cuyckens H (eds) The Oxford handbook of cognitive linguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 377–393

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela F (1996) Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. J Conscious Stud 3(4):330–350

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela F, Thompson E, Rosch E (1991) The embodied mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhagen A (2005) Constructions of Intersubjectivity. Discourse, syntax and cognition. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhagen A (2008) Intersubjectivity and the architecture of the language system. In: Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 307–332

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky LS (1978) Mind in society: the development of higer psychological processes. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1953) Philosophical investigations. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2001) Beyond empathy: phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity. J Conscious Stud 8(5–7):151–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2003) Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank R (eds) (2007) Body, language and mind. vol 1: embodiment. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Zinken J (2007) Discourse metaphors: the link between figurative and habitual analogies. Cogn Linguist 18(3):445–465

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J (1997) Situated embodiment: studies in the emergence of spatial meaning. Gotab, Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J (2005) What’s in a schema? Bodily mimesis and the grounding of language. In: Hampe B (ed) From perception to meaning: image schemas in cognitive linguistics. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 313–343

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J (2007) Embodiment, language and mimesis. In: Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank R (eds) Body, language and mind, vol 1: Embodiment. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 297–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J (2008) The dependence of language on consciousness. J Conscious Stud 15(6):34–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J, SEDSU-Project (2006) Stages in the evolution and development of sign use (SEDSU). In: Cangelosi A, Smith AD, Smith K (eds) The evolution of language: Proceedings of the 6th International Conference (EVOLANG6). World Scientific, New Jersey, pp 379–388

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) (2008) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. Benjamins, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J, Blomberg J, David C (in press) Translocation, language and the categorization of experience. In: Evans V, Chilton P (eds) Language, cognition and space . Equinox, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would wish to express my gratitude to Göran Sonesson, Esa Itkonen, Chris Sinha, the editors of this Handbook and an anonymous reviewer, whose comments on an earlier version helped improve the text considerably.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zlatev, J. (2010). Phenomenology and Cognitive Linguistics. In: Schmicking, D., Gallagher, S. (eds) Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2646-0_23

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics