Skip to main content

Self and Suffering in Buddhism and Phenomenology: Existential Pain, Compassion and the Problems of Institutional Healthcare

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Cultural Ontology of the Self in Pain

Abstract

By bringing together the Buddhist notion that suffering is intrinsic to all forms of our self-experience with Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological interpretation of selfhood in terms of the “habit-body,” I show that vulnerability and meaningfulness go hand-in-hand. I then use this developed understanding of the nature of selfhood and suffering as the basis for a critique of various foundational aspects of contemporary, institutionalized healthcare. In particular, I consider ways in which oppressive social and political practices are instituted when the existential dimensions of pain are ignored and a medical model, based on the vision of pain as an alien threat to be eliminated, is adopted instead.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the classic modern statement of the “substantial” notion of the “I”, see Descartes (1979, Second Meditation). On the relevance of this notion to Early Modern political theory, see Macpherson (1962). I have discussed political problems integral to this interpretation of persons in Russon (2015).

  2. 2.

    For a rich and full account of the phenomenological account of the “self,” see Marratto (2012) and Costello (2012). I have studied the formation of self-experience in Russon (2013b) and Russon (2014).

  3. 3.

    For a range of contemporary perspectives on the relationship between Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology and Buddhism, see Park and Kopf (2009).

  4. 4.

    Compare Saṃyutta Nikāya III.114–15. (Conze 1995, p. 75): “The instructed discipline of the Ariyans does not regard material shape as self, or self as having material shape, or material shape as being in the self, or the self as being in material shape. Nor does he regard feeling, perception, the impulses or consciousness in any of these ways. He comprehends each of the khandas as it really is that it is impermanent, suffering, not-self, compounded, murderous. He does not approach them, grasp after them or determine ‘Self for me [attā me]’ —and this for a long time conduces to welfare and happiness.”

  5. 5.

    See especially II.28 (Davids and Woodward 1917): “That being, this comes to be; from the arising of that, this arises; that being absent, this is not; from the cessation of this, this ceases”; and II.65: “That which we will, and that which we intend to do, and that for which we have a latent tendency, this is an object for the persistence of consciousness. If there is an object, there is a support for consciousness.” See also I.62 and IV.95. See Berman (2004), on the relationship between this notion (which Berman translates as “relational origination”) and Merleau-Ponty’s notion of “reversibility.”

  6. 6.

    One of the best statements of this is Husserl (2001, pp. 39–62). Compare Merleau-Ponty (2012, pp. 378–9): “When I say that I see an ashtray and that it is over there, I presuppose a complete unfolding of the experience that would have to go on indefinitely and I open up an entire perceptual future.” These themes from Husserl and Merleau-Ponty are richly developed in Howell (2015).

  7. 7.

    For the theme of space, see Husserl (1997), and Merleau-Ponty (2012), Part I, Chap. 3, “The Spatiality of One’s Own Body and Motricity.”.

  8. 8.

    For the “I can,” see Merleau-Ponty (2012, p. 139). I have studied the development of personality in these terms in Russon (2003). On the significance of this notion of “I can” in healthcare, see Schenck (1986).

  9. 9.

    In this paper, I write for convenience as if the words and ideas of the sermon are those of Siddhattha Gotama; in fact, of course, these are teachings handed down by tradition, and they may very well be the concentrated insight of generations of Buddhist thought, rather than ideas coming directly from any single individual. See Harvey (1990, pp. 3–4, 15–17).

  10. 10.

    For the five “graspings,” see Harvey (1990, pp. 49–50).

  11. 11.

    See Majjhima Nikāya, III. 203 (Horner 19541959). Within the Buddhist tradition, there is a strong emphasis on the theme of our active role in shaping matters even of birth and death; I do not extend my paralleling of Merleau-Ponty and Buddhism to this level. On this divergence with respect to Buddhist soteriology, see Berman (2004, pp. 134–135). I discuss below my understanding of the philosophical importance of the notion of karma.

  12. 12.

    See Majjhima Nikāya, 1.115, 415–16, II.114 (Horner 19541959).

  13. 13.

    Harvey (1990, p. 50). On ethics and “spontaneous right action” in Merleau-Ponty and Buddhism, see Mazis (2009), especially 196–203.

  14. 14.

    The core principles of Buddhist practice are found in “the Holy Eightfold Path,” which is “the Middle Way”; see Saṃyutta Nikāya II.43 and Majjhima Nikāya III.71–8. Compare also Krishna’s advice to Arjuna: “Be intent on action, not the the fruits of action; avoid attraction to the fruits and attachment to inaction! Perform actions, firm in discipline, relinquishing attachment; be impartial to failure and success—this equanimity is called discipline” (Bhagavad Gita 1988: Book 2, Verses 47–8). On the resources of Buddhism for dealing with pain in a medical context, see Kabat-Zinn et al. (1985).

  15. 15.

    The notion of karma is in fact inherited by Buddhism from earlier forms of Indian religion, and it is a notion shared with, for example, Hinduism. On this ancient notion, see Doniger (2009, pp. 168–170).

  16. 16.

    For these themes of temporality, see Merleau-Ponty (2012, p. 85).

  17. 17.

    I have given a phenomenological analysis of this “family” inheritence in Russon (2003), especially Chaps. 4 and 5. The stories of “blood-guilt” and its legacy in the classical Greek tragedies offer a particularly powerful reflection on these “karmic” effects. On the psychologically formative effects of families and other institutions, see Leder (2005, pp. 110–112).

  18. 18.

    Compare Pierre Bourdieu ’s notion of the social habitus: “The habitus, a product of history, produces individual and collective practices—more history—in accordance with the schemes generated by history. It ensures the active presence of past experiences, which, deposited in each organism in the form of schemes of perception, thought and action tend to guarantee the ‘correctness’ of practices and their constancy over time, more reliably than all formal rules and explicit norms” (1980, p. 54; emphasis added).

  19. 19.

    On the relevance of traditional Hindu notions of karma for the treatment of pain in medical contexts, see Whitman (2007).

  20. 20.

    I have discussed Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of the phantom limb and the implications of this analysis in Russon (2013a). See also McMahon (2014).

  21. 21.

    For Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of the phantom limb, see (2012, pp. 78–85). On this theme of the insufficiency of mind-body dualism, see Leder (2005).

  22. 22.

    On the strong parallels between Merleau-Ponty’s notion of embodiment and the Buddhist rejection of a substantial notion of self, see especially Mazis (2009; especially, 186–189).

  23. 23.

    Compare Saṃyutta Nikāya, I.135, and II. 66–68 on the inherently “non-self” character of all things.

  24. 24.

    On the theme of intersubjectivity in Merleau-Ponty and Nagarjuna, and on the relation of this to language, see Berman (2004, especially 137–141).

  25. 25.

    On the idea that pain is a meaning, see Honkasalo (2000).

  26. 26.

    I have given a phenomenological analysis of the internal dynamics of “attention” in Russon (forthcoming). See also Casey, “Attending and Glancing,” Chap. 9 (2007; especially 311–335); Vermersch (2004, pp. 52–54); and Bredlau (2006).

  27. 27.

    The International Association for the Study of Pain, for example, defines pain as “an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage, or described in terms of such damage.” On the problems with the “medical model” in dealing with pain and suffering, see Cassel (1982). For a related argument that pain is an “extra-medical” and “biocultural” phenomenon, see Morris (1991). See also Coulehan (2012), and Rawlinson (1986). On problems with the “medical model” in general, compare Goldenberg (2010).

  28. 28.

    On the limitations of this “somatogenic” model of pain, see Okifuji and Turk (1998). As they report: “The psychophysiological bases for many chronic pain syndromes are elusive. For example, no pathology is identified in over 80 % of patients with chronic back pain” (Okifuji and Turk 1998, p. 142). See also Wilde (2003), for the idea that chronic pain does not just “occur in their physical body but also in their embodiments. For such patients, dualistic (mind-body) notions of the body as object and mind as subject can devalue experiences that are necessary for healing and for managing everyday problems related to their illness or injury” (Wilde 2003, p. 170).

  29. 29.

    See Okifuji and Turk (1998, p. 143): “Many patients report that stigmatization associated with the psychogenic [“hysterical”] and motivational [“money-seeking”] models substantially adds to their suffering.”.

  30. 30.

    On the intersubjective and communal dimensions of self-experience, see Stolorow (2013); see also Russon (2003), Chap. 4.

  31. 31.

    See Minuchin et al. (1978), and Bateson (1972, pp. 225–243), “The Cybernetics of ‘Self’: A Theory of Alcoholism.” See also Laing and Esterson (1990). On the need for care itself to take the form of an intersubjective network, see Fritsch (2010).

  32. 32.

    On the suffering faced by immigrants due to separation from family, town and homeland, and the problems intrinsic to living in a new land from which one is always “absent,” see Sayad (2004).

  33. 33.

    See Fadiman (2012), for the related issues of the clash of cultures in the experience of a Hmong family’s struggle with the American hospital system following the diagnosis of epilepsy in one of their daughters. On the ambivalent value of the notion of “individual rights” in the context of different religious cultures, see Hoff (forthcoming).

  34. 34.

    For the theme of “home” in the phenomenological interpretation of the person, see Jacobson (2009).

  35. 35.

    See Jacobson (2004, 2006). For a reflection on the political implications of this interpretation of agoraphobia, see Jacobson (2011).

  36. 36.

    On the pain of “homesickness,” pertinent as much to interpersonal as to spatial relations, see Russon (2013a).

  37. 37.

    On the experiential implications of hospital architecture, see Adams et al. (2010).

  38. 38.

    On the significance of hospital architecture in general, see especially Ulrich (2000, pp. 49–59). On the stress faced by children and youth in hospital environments, see Pillitter (1987, pp. 567–578), and Korpela (2001). On the theme of permanent institutionalization of the elderly as an undermining of the experience of home and the forms of suffering related to this and to the failure of healthcare practitioners to recognize this, see Young (2005). On the distinctive experience of coming to find oneself at home in the sickbed, see Van den Berg (1966), especially Chap. 1, “The Meaning of Being Ill”.

References

  • Adams, A., Theodore, D., McLaren, C., & McKeever, P. (2010). Kids in the atrium: Comparing architectural intentions and children’s experiences in a pediatric hospital lobby. Social Sciences and Medicine, 70(5), 658–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, M. (2004). Merleau-Ponty and Nagarjuna: Relational social ontology and the ground of ethics. Asian Philosophy, 14(2), 131–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1980). The logic of practice. (R. Nice, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bredlau, S. (2006). Learning to see: Merleau-Ponty and the navigation of ‘terrains’. Chiasmi International, 8, 191–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casey, E. S. (2007). The world at a glance. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassel, E. J. (1982). The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. New England Journal of Medicine, 306(11), 639–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costello, P. (2012). Layers in Husserl’s phenomenology: On meaning and intersubjectivity. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulehan, J. (2012). Suffering, hope and healing. In R. J. Moore (Ed.), Handbook of pain and palliative care: Biobehavioral approaches to the life course (pp. 717–732). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davids, C. A. F. R., & Woodward, F. L. (Trans.). (1917). Saṃyutta Nikāya (The book of kindred sayings), 5 Vols. London: Pāli Text Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1979). Meditations on first philosophy. (D. A. Cress, Trans.) Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doniger, W. (2009). The Hindus: An alternative history. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conze, E. Horner, I. B., Snellgrove, D., & Waley, A. (Eds. & Trans.). (1995). Buddhist texts through the ages. Oxford: One World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fadiman, A. (2012). The spirit catches you and you fall down: A Hmong child, her American doctors, and the collision of two cultures. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fritsch, K. (2010). Intimate assemblages: Disability, intercorporeality, and the labour of attendant care. Critical Disability Studies, 2, 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, M. (2010). Clinical evidence and the absent body in medical phenomenology: On the need for a new phenomenology of medicine. The International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 3(1), 43–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, P. (1990). An introduction to Buddhism: Teachings, history and practices. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoff, S. (Forthcoming). Hegel and the possibility of intercultural criticism. In N. Robertson & S. Dodd (Eds.), Unity of opposites?. Hegel and Canadian political thought. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honkasalo, M. L. (2000). Chronic pain as a posture towards the world. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 41(3), 197–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horner, I. B. (Trans.). (1954–1959). Middle Length Sayings (Majjhima Nikāya), 3 Vols. London: Pali Text Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, W. (2015). Learning and the development of meaning: Husserl and Merleau-Ponty and the temporality of perception and habit. Southern Journal of Philosophy 53, 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1997). Thing and space: Lectures of 1907. (R. Rojcewicz, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic. (A. J. Steinbock, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, K. (2004). Agoraphobia and hypochondria as disorders of dwelling. International Studies in Philosophy, 36(2), 31–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, K. (2006). The interpersonal expression of human spatiality: A phenomenological interpretation of anorexia nervosa. Chiasmi International, 8: 157–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, K. (2009). A developed nature: A phenomenological account of the experience of home. Continental Philosophy Review, 42(3), 355–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, K. (2011). Embodied domestics, embodied politics: Women, home, and agoraphobia. Human Studies, 34(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kabat-Zinn, J., Lipworth, L., & Burney, R. (1985). The clinical use of mindfulness meditation for the self-regulation of chronic pain. Journal of Behavioural Medicine, 8(2), 163–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2005). Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals. (T. K. Abbott, Trans.; revised; L. Denis, Ed.). Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korpela, K. (2001). Children’s environment. In R. B. Bechtel & A. Churchman (Eds.), Handbook of environmental psychology (pp. 363–373). New York: John Wiley and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laing, R. D., & Esterson, A. (1990). Sanity, madness and the family: Families of schizophrenics. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leder, D. (2005). Moving beyond ‘mind’ and ‘body. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 12(2), 109–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, C. B. (1962). The political theory of possessive individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marratto, S. (2012). The intercorporeal self: Merleau-Ponty on subjectivity. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazis, G. (2009). The flesh of the world is emptiness and emptiness is the flesh of the world, and their ethical implications. In J. Y. Park & G. Kopf (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty and Buddhism (pp. 183–208). Lanham MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahon, L. (2014). The Phantom Organic: Merleau-Ponty and the Psychoanalysis of Nature. Chiasmi International 16, 275–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception (D. A. Landes, Trans.). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. S. (Trans.). (1988). Bhagavad Gita. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minuchin, S., Rosman, B. L., & Baker, L. (1978). Psychosomatic families: Anorexia Nervosa in context. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. B. (1991). The culture of pain. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okifuji, A., & Turk, D. C. (1998). Philosophy and efficacy of multidisciplinary approach to chronic pain management. Journal of Anesthesia, 12(3), 142–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, J. Y., & Kopf, G. (Eds.). (2009). Merleau-Ponty and Buddhism. Lanham MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pillitter, A. (1987). Child health nursing. Boston: Little Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawlinson, M. C. (1986). The sense of suffering. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 11(1), 39–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russon, J. (2003). Human experience: Philosophy, neurosis, and the elements of everyday life. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russon, J. (2013a). Haunted by history: Merleau-Ponty, Hegel, and the phenomenology of pain. Journal of Contemporary Thought, 37, 81–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russon, J. (2013b). The virtues of agency: A phenomenology of confidence, courage, and creativity. In K. Hermberg & P. Gyllenhammer (Eds.), Phenomenology and virtue ethics (pp. 165–179). New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russon, J. (2014). Between two intimacies: The formative contexts of individual experience. Emotion, Space and Society, 13, 65–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russon, J. (2015) On secrets and sharing: Hegel, Heidegger and Derrida on the economics of the public sphere. In V. Sanil & D. Dwivedi (Eds.), Public sphere from outside the west (pp. 41–57). New Delhi: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russon, J. (Forthcoming). Freedom and passivity: Attention, work and language. In K. Jacobson & J. Russon (Eds.), Perception and its development in Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayad, A. (2004). The suffering of the immigrant (D. Macey, Trans.). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schenck, D. (1986). The texture of embodiment: Foundation for medical ethics. Human Studies, 9(1), 43–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stolorow, R. (2013). Intersubjective systems-theory: A phenomenological-contextualist psychoanalytic perspective. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 23(4), 383–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talero, M. (2005). Perception, normativity, and selfhood in Merleau-Ponty: The spatial ‘level’ and existential space. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 43(3), 443–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulrich, R. S. (2000). Effects of healthcare environmental design on medical outcomes. In Design and health—The therapeutic benefits of design, Proceedings of the 2nd Annual International Congress on Design and Health. Stockholm: Karolinska Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Berg, J. H. (1966). The psychology of the sickbed. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermersch, P. (2004). Attention between phenomenology and experimental psychology. Continental Philosophy Review, 37(1), 45–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, S. M. (2007). Pain and suffering as viewed by the Hindu religion. The Journal of Pain, 8(8), 607–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilde, M. H. (2003). Embodied knowledge in chronic illness and injury. Nursing Inquiry, 10(3), 170–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. M.. (2005). A room of one’s own: Old age, extended care, and privacy. In I. M. Young, On female body experience: “Throwing like a girl” and other essays (pp. 155–70). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Russon .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer India

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Russon, J. (2016). Self and Suffering in Buddhism and Phenomenology: Existential Pain, Compassion and the Problems of Institutional Healthcare. In: George, S., Jung, P. (eds) Cultural Ontology of the Self in Pain. Springer, New Delhi. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-81-322-2601-7_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics