Advertisement

Converging on the Self: Western Philosophy, Eastern Meditation and Scientific Research

  • Jonathan Shear
Chapter

Abstract

Descartes, Hume and Kant all emphasized knowledge of self, holding it to be the “Archimedes point” of knowledge, the “capital or centre” of science and the “supreme principle” of employment of the understanding, respectively. Their analyses of what the self is, however, conflict strongly. Descartes held it to be single, simple, unimaginable and continuing. Hume argued we have no experience of anything corresponding to this idea. Kant supported Descartes by arguing that self as single, simple, unimaginable and continuing is absolutely necessary. But, strengthening Hume, he also argued that this idea of self is necessarily vacuous. For to accompany every possible experience, the self would have to be devoid of empirical properties of its own. And such a qualityless “pure consciousness” cannot even be coherently conceived, much less experienced. The topic remains problematic for Western philosophy.

Eastern traditions, by contrast, argue that while experience of “pure consciousness” cannot properly be imagined, it can actually be had. Meditation procedures can allow all ordinary mental activity to settle down and disappear, while one nevertheless remains awake. What remains is consciousness itself, devoid of empirical properties. This experience uniquely allows major features of Descartes, Hume and Kant’s analyses of self to be rendered consistent. And their analyses in turn identify the experience as being of self.

Empirical research appears to support this conclusion. Physiological correlates indicate that the experience reflects an innate potential of human consciousness, and link it to the brain’s default mode network thought to underlie our natural sense of self.

Keywords

Default Mode Network Western Philosophy Transcendental Meditation Pure Consciousness Default Mode Network Activity 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Anscombe, E. & Geach, P. T. (1971). Descartes: Philosophical writings. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
  2. Badawi, K., Wallace, R. K., Orme-Johnson, D., & Rouzere, A. M. (1984). Electrophysiologic characteristics of respiratory suspension periods occurring during the practice of the Transcendental Meditation program. Psychosomatic Medicine, 46(3), 267–276.Google Scholar
  3. Gallagher, S., & Shear, J. (Eds.). (1999). Models of the self. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  4. Hume, D. (1978). In L. A. Selby-Bigge (Ed.), Treatise of human nature (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Kant, I. (1964). Critique of pure reason (N. K. Smith, Trans.). New York: Macmillan & Co. pp. 165–328Google Scholar
  6. Orme-Johnson, D. W., & Haynes, C. T. (1981). EEG phase coherence, pure consciousness, creativity, and TM-Sidhi experiences. International Journal of Neuroscience, 13(4), 211–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Shear, J. (1990a). The inner dimension. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
  8. Shear, J. (1990b). Mystical experience, hermeneutics, and rationality. International Philosophical Quarterly, 30(4), 391–401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Shear, J. (1998). Experiential clarification of the problem of self. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(5/6), 673–686.Google Scholar
  10. Shear, J. (2006). The experience of meditation: Experts introduce the major traditions. St. Paul: Paragon House.Google Scholar
  11. Shear, J. (2011, Summer). State-enlivening and practice-makes-perfect approaches to meditation. Biofeedback: A Clinical Journal, 39(2), 51–55.Google Scholar
  12. Travis, F., & Pearson, C. (2000). Pure consciousness: Distinct phenomenological and physiological correlates of ‘Consciousness Itself’. International Journal of Neuroscience, 100(1–4), 77–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Travis, F., & Wallace, R. K. (1997). Autonomic patterns during respiratory suspensions: Possible markers of transcendental consciousness. Psychophysiology, 34(1), 39–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Travis, F., Haaga, D. A. F., Hagelin, J., Tanner, M., Arenander, A., Nidich, S., Gaylord-King, C., Grosswald, S., Rainforth, M., & Schneider, R. H. (2010). A self-referential default brain state: Patterns of coherence, power, and eLORETA sources during eyes-closed rest and Transcendental Meditation practice. Cognitive Processing, 11(1), 21–30.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer India 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyVirginia Commonwealth UniversityRichmondUSA

Personalised recommendations