Skip to main content

Abstract

The standard revealed preference argument relies on an implicit assumption that a decision maker considers all feasible alternatives. However, the marketing and psychology literatures provide well-established evidence that consumers do not consider all brands in a given market before making a purchase (Limited Attention). In this chapter, we illustrate how one can deduce both the decision maker’s preference and the alternatives to which she pays attention and inattention from the observed behavior. We illustrate how seemingly compelling welfare judgements without specifying the underlying choice procedure are misleading. Further, we provide a choice theoretical foundation for maximizing a single preference relation under limited attention.

The original article first appeared in the American Economic Review 102(5):2183–2205, 2012. A newly written addendum has been added to this book chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Varian (2006) provides a nice survey of revealed preference analysis.

  2. 2.

    As argued in Aumann (2005), this behavior is still considered rational (at least boundedly rational) since she is choosing the best alternative under her limited information about what is available.

  3. 3.

    Lavidge and Steiner (1961) presented awareness of an item as a necessary condition to be in the consideration set. How unawareness alters the behavior of the DM has been studied in various contexts such as game theory (Heifetz et al., 2010, Dynamic unawareness and rationalizable behavior, unpublished; Ozbay, 2008, Unawareness and strategic announcements in games with uncertainty, unpublished), and contract theory (Filiz-Ozbay, 2010, Incorporating awareness into contract theory, unpublished).

  4. 4.

    In addition, in financial economics it is shown that investors reach a decision within their limited attention (Huberman and Regev 2001). Similar examples can be found in job search (Richards et al. 1975), university choice (Dawes and Brown 2005), and airport choice (Basar and Bhat 2004).

  5. 5.

    Without any structure on the formation of the consideration sets, any choice behavior can be rationalized by any preference (Hausman 2008).

  6. 6.

    See Ambrus and Rozen (2010, Rationalizing choice with multi-self models, unpublished), Apesteguia and Ballester (2010, A measure of rationality and welfare, unpublished), Cherepanov et al. (2010, Rationalization, unpublished), Chambers and Hayashi (2008), Green and Hojman (2008), Manzini and Mariotti (2012), Masatlioglu and Nakajima (2009, Choice by iterative search, unpublished), Noor (2011), and Rubinstein and Salant (2009).

  7. 7.

    Indeed, Bernheim and Rangel (2007) mention that if we know the DM believes that she is choosing from a set that is other than the objective feasible set, we should take it into account for the welfare analysis (Section III B).

  8. 8.

    While this paper is complementary to our paper, their implications are completely different We discuss it in the Conclusion section.

  9. 9.

    Throughout the paper, unless it leads to confusion, we abuse the notation by suppressing set delimiters, e.g. writing c(xy) instead of c({x, y}) or Γ(xy) instead of Γ({x, y}) or Sx instead of S∖{x}.

  10. 10.

    The only exception is that the feasible set itself conveys some information that affects her belief or cost function.

  11. 11.

    Salant and Rubinstein (2008) characterizes this class of choice functions by assuming N is observable.

  12. 12.

    This heuristic is very close to “Rationalization” of Cherepanov et al. (2010, Rationalization, unpublished). Indeed, it is a special version of Rationalization. In their model, unlike “the top on each criterion”, depending on the feasible set, different sets of criteria might be utilized to eliminate alternatives in the first stage. See Sect. 4 for further discussion.

  13. 13.

    For instance, suppose store A deals with Makers 1 and 2’s bikes while store B sells bikes from Makers 2 and 3. Then, the DM compares the number of Makers 1 and 2’s bikes with that of Makers 2 and 3’s to choose which store to visit.

  14. 14.

    That is, c(S) ∈ Γ(S) and \(c(S) \succ x\) for all \(x \in \varGamma (S)\setminus c(S)\).

  15. 15.

    In the extreme case where the choice data satisfy the weak axiom of revealed preference, we have no way of knowing whether the decision maker is aware of all alternatives and maximizing a particular preference, or whether she only pays attention to the one she chooses. In the latter, her preference has no significant importance. In Sect. 6, we discuss the situations where one can pin down the preference even in this extreme case.

  16. 16.

    For a detailed discussion of this subject, see Manzini and Mariotti (2009, Choice based welfare economics for boundedly rational agents, unpublished).

  17. 17.

    “The top on each criterion” introduced in Sect. 2.1 coincides with the rationalization model when all rationales are complete.

  18. 18.

    Actually, Manzini and Mariotti (2007) do not require the second rationale (P 2) to be complete and transitive (it only requires P 2 to be asymmetric). We put the stronger requirement on P 2 in order to highlight that the difference between these models is generated by the first stage, not by the incompleteness or intransitivity of the second rationale, which corresponds to the DM’s preference in our model.

  19. 19.

    One can show that if P 1 is transitive, the first stage elimination generates an attention filter so the resulting choice will be a CLA as long as P 2 is complete and transitive.

  20. 20.

    This phenomenon is well-documented and robust in behavioral research on marketing (Huber et al. 1982; Tversky and Simonson 1993), including choices among monetary gambles, political candidates, job candidates, environmental issues, and medical decision making. Advertising irrelevant alternatives is commonly used as a marketing strategy to invoke the attraction effect on the customers.

  21. 21.

    The standard continuity is inconsistent with the attraction effect: x = c(x, d n , y) for all n but y is chosen at the limit (y = c(x, y)) where {d n } is a sequence of x’s decoys converging to x. Nevertheless, the model can still enjoy a weaker continuity along with the attraction effect. For example, assume \(y_{n} \rightarrow y\) and \(y,y_{n}\not\in S,\) then

    $$\displaystyle{ \mbox{ If }y_{n}\not\in c(S \cup y_{n})\mbox{ then }\{y\}\neq c(S \cup y_{n}). }$$

    Indeed, one can show that the CLA is continuous in this sense if \(\succ \) is continuous and the attention filter satisfies: (a) \(y_{n}\not\in \varGamma (S \cup y_{n})\) implies \(y\not\in \varGamma (S \cup y)\) and (b) \(z \in \varGamma (S \cup y_{n})\) implies \(z \in \varGamma (S \cup y)\) when \(y_{n} \rightarrow y\).

  22. 22.

    Eliaz and Spiegler (2011) studied a game theoretical model where firms would like to influence consumers’ consideration sets by introducing costly decoys.

  23. 23.

    This generalized attraction effect is another example that lies outside of recent models provided in Cherepanov et al. 2008, Manzini and Mariotti (2012) and Lleras et al. (2010, When more is less: choice by limited consideration, unpublished) since it does not satisfy Weak-WARP. There are two exceptions: Ok et al. (2010, Revealed (p)reference theory, unpublished) and de Clippel and Eliaz (2012). However, these two models can accommodate neither Cyclical nor Choosing Pairwisely choice patterns.

  24. 24.

    In this regard, our theory highlights the importance of other tools (besides observed choice) which can shed light on the choice process rather than outcome.

  25. 25.

    This order is not necessarily complete, as in this example; Michigan does not compare its students with candidates from other schools.

  26. 26.

    Nakajima appreciates the financial support provided by Japan Society for the Promotion of Science (JSPS KAKENHI Grant Number 26780113).

References

  • Aumann RJ (2005) Musings on information and knowledge. Econ J Watch 2(1):88–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Basar G, Bhat C (2004) A parameterized consideration set model for airport choice: an application to the San Francisco bay area. Trans Res Part B Methodol 38(10):889–904

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim BD, Rangel A (2007) Toward choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. Am Econ Rev 97(2):464–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim BD, Rangel A (2009) Beyond revealed preference: choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. Q J Econ 124(1):51–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent DE (1958) Perception and communication. Pergamon, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caplin A, Dean M (2011) Search, choice, and revealed preference. Theor Econ 6:19–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplin A, Dean M, Martin D (2009) Search and satisficing. Am Econ Rev 101:2899–2922. doi: 10.1257/aer.101.7.2899

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers CP, Hayashi T (2008) Choice and individual welfare. HSS California Institute of Technology Working Paper 1286

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherepanov V, Feddersen T, Sandroni A (2013) Rationalization. Theor Econ 8:775–800

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chetty R, Looney A, Kroft K (2009) Salience and taxation: theory and evidence. Am Econ Rev 99(4):1145–1177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiang J, Chib S, Narasimhan C (1998) Markov chain Monte Carlo and models of consideration set and parameter heterogeneity. J Econ 89(1–2):223–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawes PL, Brown J (2005) The composition of consideration and choice sets in undergraduate university choice: an exploratory study. J Market High Educ 14(2):37–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Clippel G, Eliaz K (2012) Reason-based choice: a bargaining rationale for the attraction and compromise effects. Theor Econ 7:125–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Clippel G, Rozen K (2014) Bounded rationality and limited datasets. Mimeo. http://www.econ.brown.edu/fac/Geoffroy_declippel/GK_BRLimitedData.pdf

  • DellaVigna S, Pollet J (2007) Demographics and industry returns. Am Econ Rev 97:1167–1702

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dulleck U, Hackl F, Weiss B, Winter-Ebmer R (2008) Buying online: sequential decision making by shopbot visitors. Wien economics series, vol 225. Institut für Höhere Studien

    Google Scholar 

  • Eliaz K, Spiegler R (2011) Consideration sets and competitive marketing. Rev Econ Stud 78(1):235–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliaz K, Richter M, Rubinstein A (2011) An etude in choice theory: choosing the two finalists. Econ Theory 46(2):211–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabaix X, Laibson D, Moloche G, Weinberg S (2006) Costly information acquisition: experimental analysis of a boundedly rational model. Am Econ Rev 96(4):1043–1068

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goeree MS (2008) Limited information and advertising in the US personal computer industry. Econometrica 76:1017–1074

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green JR, Hojman D (2008) Choice, rationality and welfare measurement. Harvard Institute of Economic Research Discussion Paper No. 2144

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser JR, Wernerfelt B (1990) An evaluation cost model of evoked sets. J Consum Res 16:383–408

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman D (2008) Mindless or mindfull economics: a methodological evaluation. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics: a handbook. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 125–155

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Houy N (2007) Rationality and order-dependent sequential rationality. Theory Decis 62(2):119–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houy N, Tadenuma K (2009) Lexicographic compositions of multiple criteria for decision making. J Econ Theory 144(4):1770–1782

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber J, Payne JW, Puto C (1982) Adding asymmetrically dominated alternatives: violations of regularity and the similarity hypothesis. J Consum Res 9(1):90–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huberman G, Regev T (2001) Contagious speculation and a cure for cancer: a nonevent that made stock prices soar. J Financ 56(1):387–396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iwata Y (2013) Generalized revealed attention. Mimeo, Nishogakusha University, Tokyo

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavidge RJ, Steiner GA (1961) A model for predictive measurements of advertising effectiveness. J Market 25:59–62

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann DR, Pan Y (1994) Context effects, new brand entry, and consideration sets. J Market Res 31(3):364–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes G, Starmer C, Sugden R (1991) Observing violations of transitivity by experimental methods. Econometrica 59(2):425–439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini P, Mariotti M (2007) Sequentially rationalizable choice. Am Econ Rev 97(5):1824–1839

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini P, Mariotti M (2009) Choice over time. In: Anand P, Pattanaik P, Puppe C (eds) Oxford handbook of rational and social choice, chapter 10. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzini P, Mariotti M (2012) Categorize then choose: boundedly rational choice and welfare. J Eur Econ Assoc 10(5). doi: 10.2307/23251215.

  • Masatlioglu Y, Nakajima D, Ozbay EY (2012) Revealed attention. Am Econ Rev 102(5):2183–2205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May KO (1954) Intransitivity, utility, and the aggregation of preference patterns. Econometrica 22:1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noor J (2011) Temptation and revealed preference. Econometrica 79(2):601–644

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pessemier EA (1978) Stochastic properties of changing preferences. Am Econ Rev 68(2):380–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards MD, Sheridan JE, Slocum JW (1975) Comparative analysis of expectancy and heuristic models of decision behavior. J Appl Psychol 60(3):361–368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts JH, Lattin JM (1991) Development and testing of a model of consideration set composition. J Market Res 28(4):429–440

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein A, Salant Y (2009) Eliciting welfare preferences from behavioral datasets. Rev Econ Stud 79(1). doi: 10.2307/41407054.

  • Salant Y, Rubinstein A (2008) Choice with frames. Rev Econ Stud 75:1287–1296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA (1938) A note on the pure theory of consumers’ behavior. Econometrica (February) 61–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1957) Models of man: social and rational: mathematical essays on rational human behavior in a social setting. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sims CA (2003) Implications of rational inattention. J Monet Econ 50(3):665–690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler GJ (1961) The economics of information. J Politi Econ 69(3):213–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teppan EC, Felfernig A (2009) Minimization of product utility estimation errors in recommender result set evaluations. In: WI-IAT 2009 proceedings of the 2009 IEEE/ WIC/ACM international joint conference on web intelligence and intelligent agent technology, vol 1. University of Milano-Bicocca, Milan, pp 20–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A (1969) Intransitivity of preferences. Psychol Rev 76:31–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A, Simonson I (1993) Context-dependent preferences. Manag Sci 39(10):1179–1189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varian HR (2006) Revealed preference. In: Szenberg M, Ramrattan L, Gottesman AA (eds) Samuelsonian economics and the twenty-first century. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 99–115

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wright P, Barbour F (1977) Phased decision strategies: sequels to an initial screening. In: Starr MK, Zeleny M (eds) Studies in management sciences, multiple criteria decision making. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 91–109

    Google Scholar 

  • Zyman S (1999) The end of marketing as we know it. Harper Collins, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daisuke Nakajima .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendix

1.1 Proofs

Notice that the if-parts of Theorems 1 and 2 have been already shown in the main text. The following proofs use these results.

1.1.1 Proof of Theorem 3

Suppose c is a CLA represented by \((\succ,\varGamma )\). Then Theorem 1(if part) implies that \(\succ \) must include P so P must be acyclic. Therefore, by Lemma 1, c must satisfy WARP(LA).

Now suppose that c satisfies WARP(LA). By Lemma 1, P is acyclic so there is a preference \(\succ \) that includes P. Pick any such preference arbitrarily and define

$$\displaystyle{ \varGamma (S) =\{ x \in S\:\ c(S) \succ x\} \cup \{ c(S)\}. }$$
(19.2)

Then, it is clear that c(S) is the unique \(\succ \)-best element in Γ(S) so all we need to show is that Γ is an attention filter. Suppose x ∈ S but \(x\not\in \varGamma (S)\) (so xc(S)). By construction, \(x \succ c(S)\) so it cannot be c(S)Px. Hence, it must be \(c(S) = c(S\setminus x)\) so we have \(\varGamma (S) =\varGamma (S\setminus x)\). \(\square \)

1.1.2 Proof of Theorem 1 (The Only-If Part)

Suppose xP Ry does not hold. Then there exists a preference that includes P R and ranks y better than x. The proof of Theorem 3 shows that c can be represented by such a preference so x is not revealed to be preferred to y. \(\square \)

1.1.3 Proof of Theorem 2 (The Only-If Parts)

(Revealed Inattention) Suppose x is not revealed to be preferred to c(S). Then pick a preference that includes P R and puts c(S) above x. The proof of Theorem 3 shows that c can be represented by such a preference and an attention filter Γ with x ∈ Γ(S).

(Revealed Attention) Suppose there exists no T which satisfies the condition. We shall prove that if c is a CLA then it can be represented by some attention filter Γ with \(x\not\in \varGamma (S)\). If c(S)P R x does not hold, we have already shown that c can be represented with \(x \succ c(S)\) and \(x\not\in \varGamma (S)\) so x is not revealed to attract attention at S, so we focus on the case when c(S)P R x.

Now construct a binary relation, \(\tilde{P}\), where \(a\tilde{P}b\) if and only if “aP R b” or “a = c(S) and not bP R c(S).” That is, \(\tilde{P}\) puts c(S) as high as possible as long as it does not contradict P R . Since P R is acyclic and c is represented by an attention filter, one can show that \(\tilde{P}\) is also acyclic. Given this, take any preference relation \(\succ \) that includes \(\tilde{P}\), which includes P R as well. We have already shown that \(\tilde{\varGamma }(S) \equiv \{ z \in S: c(S) \succ z\} \cup \{ c(S)\}\) is an attention filter and \((\tilde{\varGamma },\succ )\) represents c. Now define Γ as follows:

$$\displaystyle{ \varGamma \left (S^{{\prime}}\right ) = \left \{\begin{array}{cc} \tilde{\varGamma }\left (S^{{\prime}}\right ) & \mbox{ for }\ S^{{\prime}}\notin \mathcal{D}, \\ \tilde{\varGamma }\left (S^{{\prime}}\right )\setminus x&\mbox{ for }\ S^{{\prime}}\in \mathcal{D}, \end{array} \right. }$$

where \(\mathcal{D}\) is a collections of sets such that

$$\displaystyle{ \mathcal{D} =\left \{S^{{\prime}}\subset X: \begin{array}{cc} c\left (S^{{\prime}}\right ) = c\left (S\right )\mbox{ } &\,\mbox{ and} \\ \mathit{zP}_{R}c\left (S\,\right )\ \mbox{ for all }\ z \in \left (S\setminus S^{{\prime}}\right ) \cup \left (S^{{\prime}}\setminus S\right ).& \end{array} \right \} }$$

That is, Γ is obtained from \(\tilde{\varGamma }\) by removing from x any budget set \(S^{{\prime}}\) where \(c(S) = c(S^{{\prime}})\) and any item that belongs to S or \(S^{{\prime}}\) but not to both is revealed to be better than c(S). Notice that x cannot be c(S) because if this true, the condition of the statement is satisfied for T = S. Hence, \(\varGamma (S^{{\prime}}) \subset \tilde{\varGamma } (S^{{\prime}})\) always includes \(c(S^{{\prime}})\). Furthermore the proof of Theorem 3 shows that \((\tilde{\varGamma },\succ )\) represents c. Therefore, \((\varGamma,\succ )\) also represents c so we only need to show that Γ is an attention filter.

To do that, it is useful to notice that \(\tilde{\varGamma }\) is an attention filter and \(c(T^{{\prime}}) = c(T^{{\prime\prime}})\) whenever \(\tilde{\varGamma }(T^{{\prime}}) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T^{{\prime\prime}})\) because \((\tilde{\varGamma },\succ )\) represents c.

Suppose \(y\not\in \varGamma (T)\). We shall prove \(\varGamma (T) =\varGamma (T\setminus y)\).

  • Case I: y = x

    If \(T\not\in \mathcal{D}\), then we have \(\varGamma (T) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T\setminus x) =\varGamma (T\setminus x)\). If \(T \in \mathcal{D}\), then it must be \(c(T) = c(T\setminus x)\) (otherwise, the condition of the statement is satisfied) so by construction of \(\tilde{\varGamma }\) and Γ, we have \(\varGamma (T) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T)\setminus x =\tilde{\varGamma } (T\setminus x) =\varGamma (T\setminus x).\)

  • Case II: \(T \in \mathcal{D}\) and yx

    Since \(y\not\in \varGamma (T)\) is equivalent to \(y\not\in \tilde{\varGamma }(T)\), we have \(\tilde{\varGamma }(T) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T\setminus y)\). Therefore, \(c(T\setminus y) = c(T) = c(S)\). By construction of Γ and \(\tilde{\varGamma }\), it must be \(y \succ c(S)\), which implies yP Rc (S) by construction of \(\succ \). Therefore, \(T\setminus y \in \mathcal{D}\). Therefore, \(\varGamma (T) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T)\setminus x =\tilde{\varGamma } (T\setminus y)\setminus x =\varGamma (T\setminus y)\).

  • Case III: \(T\not\in \mathcal{D}\) and yx

    If \(T\setminus y \in \mathcal{D}\), analogously to the previous case, we have \(c(T) = c(T\setminus y) = c(S)\) and yP R c(S) so it must be \(T \in \mathcal{D}\), which is a contradiction. Hence, \(T\setminus y\not\in \mathcal{D}\) so we have \(\varGamma (T) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T) =\tilde{\varGamma } (T\setminus y) =\varGamma (T\setminus y)\). \(\square \)

Addendum

This addendum has been newly written by Daisuke Nakajima for this book chapter.

The article in this chapter, since first presented in 2008, have triggered many interesting studies.Footnote 26 It is not possible to address all of them so I am presenting two most closely related ones in this addendum.

2.1 Incorporating Auxiliary Data

As we discuss in Sect. 6, it is not always possible to completely elicit DM’s preference from her choice data, which contains only pairs of a feasible set and her choice. In many environments, we can access data beyond feasible sets. For instance, marketing analysts knows the amount of time and money spent on advertisements for each product.

Consider the following situation. The DM chooses x from a certain set of alternatives. Now her choice suddenly shifts to y when a third product z is more advertised. I argue that she prefers y to z. To see this, suppose she does not pay attention to z in the latter environment. Then, it is hard to imagine she does so in the former case where z is less advertised. Thus, z is never considered in neither environment. Extending the idea of attention filters, I conclude that the advertising such an ignored product will not affect her attention span, so should not cause the choice shift. This is a contradiction so she must have considered z when it is more advertised. Thus, we can conclude she prefers y to z.

Iwata (2013) generalizes this idea, which illustrates how to utilize observable salience factors possessed by each alternative in each decision problem. Iwata’s model, called generalized CLA, consists of a stable preference and a consideration set mapping like our original CLA model. The difference is that Iwata’s consideration set mapping now depends not only on a feasible set but also on salience factors of all alternatives. Adapting the idea of our attention filter, Iwata requires DM’s attention filter unaffected when an unconsidered alternative is removed or when an unconsidered alternative’s salience decreases. Iwata defines revealed preference, attention and inattention as we do, and characterizes them like our Theorems 1 and 2.

2.2 Limited Data

We assume all choice data are available. That is, DM’s choices from all subsets of X are all observed. Although this requirement is not uncommon among the theoretical literatures, it sounds too much in many of empirical and experimental settings.

The lack of complete choice data does not undermine the effectiveness of our identification. We can conclude that the DM prefers x to y based only on as few as two decision problems. Nevertheless, de Clippel and Rozen (2014) illustrates Theorems 1 and 3 cannot be literally extended when choice data is limited. Example 2 in their study demonstrates this issue as follows. Suppose there are five potentially available alternatives a, b, d, e, f, but we observe only five choice data:

$$\displaystyle{ c(\mathit{ae}) = e,\ \ c(\mathit{ef }) = f,\ \ c(\mathit{abd}) = d,\ \ c(\mathit{ade}) = a.c(\mathit{bde}) = b. }$$

Suppose c is a CLA. This data contains only one choice reversals (between ade and ad) so \(a \succ d\) seems the only revealed preference.

We can, however, also conclude that the DM prefers b to e. Imagine that the DM faced another binary decision problem between b and d. He would choose d. To see this, note that \(a\not\in \varGamma (\mathit{ade})\) because \(a \succ c(\mathit{ade}) = d\). Thus, removing a would not affect her consideration span nor her choice so it would be c(bd) = d. Notice that we observe c(bde) = b so removing e from bde, although it is not actually observed, would cause a choice reversal. Considering these hypothetical choices, we must conclude she prefers b over e. This example shows that, when the choice data is limited, Theorem 1 overlooks some identifiable parts of the DM’s preference.

Now imagine that we have one more extra choice data c(bef ) = e, which is the original version of Example 2 in Clippel and Rozen’s paper. This extra information, together with c(ef ) = d, makes it possible to identify \(e \succ b\). This does not sound a contradiction if we do not imagine that the DM could face the choice between b and d. Thus one may wonder these six data are compatible with the CLA model but we have already shown that the first five data reveals \(b \succ e\) by considering the hypothetical binary choice. In sum, this example illustrates that data seemingly satisfying the WALP(LA) may not be explained by the CLA model.

de Clippel and Rozen (2014) emphasize the second issue, and propose the remedy of the behavioral characterization of the CLA model (Proposition 2). Nevertheless, they remark that their results illustrates a weakness of our theory as follows:

Being subject to this pitfall is not a weakness of a theory. Rather, the moral is that one cannot limit the test of consistency to finding a story that explains the observed data, without thinking whether that story extends. This extensibility problem is precisely avoided (for any theory) by employing Definition 1.

In line with their remark, I would like to emphasize the following point: the first issue (the overlooked revealed preference) shows that our model can generate more preference information by the careful investigations rather than mindlessly applying Theorem 1. It does not show a pitfall of but a power of our model, which is more than it appears to have.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Japan

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Masatlioglu, Y., Nakajima, D., Ozbay, E.Y. (2016). Revealed Attention. In: Ikeda, S., Kato, H., Ohtake, F., Tsutsui, Y. (eds) Behavioral Economics of Preferences, Choices, and Happiness. Springer, Tokyo. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-4-431-55402-8_19

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics