Skip to main content

Species of Abductive Reasoning in Fact Investigation in Law

  • Chapter
The Dynamics of Judicial Proof

Part of the book series: Studies in Fuzziness and Soft Computing ((STUDFUZZ,volume 94))

Abstract

Imaginative reasoning is as vital in law as it is in any other discipline. During fact investigation, hypotheses, in the form of possible charges or complaints, must be generated or discovered, as well as evidence bearing on these hypotheses. During the later process of proof, arguments in defense of the relevance, credibility, and probative force of offered evidence on hypotheses must also be generated. In no context known to me are hypotheses, evidence, and arguments linking them supplied at the outset for investigators and attorneys. These ingredients must be generated by imaginative or creative thinking. How we are able to generate new ideas has been an object of study for millennia. In spite of this, our imaginative and creative reasoning abilities are not well understood. There is considerable debate about the forms of reasoning that take place as we generate new ideas and evidential tests of them. This Article concerns a form of reasoning called “abduction,” which was suggested over a century ago by the American philosopher Charles S. Peirce as a reasoning mechanism underlying imaginative and creative thought. Most of us hear about two forms of reasoning: (1) deduction, showing that something is necessarily true, and (2) induction,showing that something is probably true. There is reason to believe that new ideas, in the form of hypotheses, may not be generated by induction or deduction. In this Article I will suggest that there are several species of abductive reasoning by which we show that something is possibly or plausibly true. I relate these species of abduction to intellectual tasks performed by investigators during fact investigation and to those performed by advocates during the process of proof. Consideration of these species of abductive reasoning exposes the richness of this important discovery-related activity.

The research upon which this Article is based was supported by Information Extraction and Transport, Inc. under Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency Contract # DACA 76-97-C-0005. The author is especially grateful to Dr. Tod Levitt for his encouragement and support.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. DAVID A. BINDER & PAUL BERGMAN, FACT INVESTIGATION: FROM HYPOTHESIS TO PROOF (1984) (discussing the various intellectual requisites of successful fact investigation).

    Google Scholar 

  2. TERENCE ANDERSON & WILLIAM TWINING, ANALYSIS OF EVIDENCE: How TO Do THINGS WITH FACTS BASED ON WIGMORE’S SCIENCE OF JUDICIAL PROOF (1998) (discussing the properties, uses, discovery, and marshaling of evidence in the context of law).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See David A. Schum, Marshaling Thoughts and Evidence During Fact Investigation, 40 S. TEx L. REV. 401–54 (1999) (discussing alternative strategies for marshaling thoughts and evidence during fact investigation).

    Google Scholar 

  4. See ANDERSON & TWINING, supra note 2, at 83–85, 94, 164, 443.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Id. at 443.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Id. at 9–15.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See JOHN HENRY WIGMORE, THE SCIENCE OF JUDICIAL PROOF AS GIVEN BY LOGIC, PSYCHOLOGY, AND GENERAL EXPERIENCE AND ILLUSTRATED IN JUDICIAL TRIALS (3d ed. 1937 ).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See DAVID OLDROYD, THE ARCH OF KNOWLEDGE: AN INTRODUCTORY STUDY OF THE HISTORY OF THE PHILOSOPHY AND METHODOLOGY OF SCIENCE (1986) (explaining the process of scientific inquiry and reviewing the distinction between generating and justifying hypotheses).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See MORRIS R. COHEN & ERNEST NAGLE, AN INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC AND SCIENTIFIC METHOD 274–75 (1934); WILLIAM KNEALE, PROBABILITY AND INDUCTION 30–37 (1949).

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Schum, supra note 3, at 419–23.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See CHARLES SANDERS PEIRCE, REASONING AND THE LOGIC OF THINGS: THE CAMBRIDGE CONFERENCES LECTURES OF 1898 (Kenneth L. Ketner ed., 1992); CHARLES SANDERS PEIRCE, Abduction and Induction, in PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS OF PEIRCE 150–51 (Justus Buchler ed., 1955 ) [hereinafter PEIRCE, Abduction and Induction]; CHARLES SANDERS PEIRCE, Perceptual Judgments, in PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS OF PEIRCE, supra, at 302–09.

    Google Scholar 

  12. UMBERTO Eco & THOMAS A. Sebeok, The Sign Of Three: DUPIN, HOLMES, PEIRCE (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  13. NORWOOD RUSSELL HANSON, PATTERNS OF DISCOVERY: AN INQUIRY INTO THE CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATIONS OF SCIENCE (1958); NICHOLAS RESCHER, PEIRCE’S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE: CRITICAL STUDIES IN HIS THEORY OF INDUCTION AND SCIENTIFIC METHOD ( 1978 ); Richard Tursman, Peirce’S Theory Of Scientific Discovery: A System Of Logic Conceived As Semiotic (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  14. See, e.g., J.R. JOSEPHSON & S.G. JOSEPHSON, ABDUCTIVE INFERENCE: COMPUTATION, PHILOSOPHY, TECHNOLOGY (1994); Y. Peng & J.A. Reggia, A Probabilistic Causal Model for Diagnostic Problem Solving — Part I1: Diagnostic Strategy, in 17 IEEE

    Google Scholar 

  15. TRANSACTIONS ON SYSTEMS, MAN, AND CYBERNETICS 395 (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  16. I5 See 4 RYSZARD MICHALSKI & GHEORGHE TECUCI, MACHINE LEARNING: A MULTISTRATEGY APPROACH 19–20 (1994).

    Google Scholar 

  17. See PEIRCE, Abduction and Induction, supra note 11, at 152–53.

    Google Scholar 

  18. DAVID HACKETT FISCHER, HISTORIANS’ FALLACIES: TOWARD A LOGIC OF HISTORICAL THOUGHT xvi (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  19. See, e.g., UMBERTO ECO, SEMIOTICS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE UMBERTO ECO, A THEORY OF SEMIOTICS (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  20. See, e.g., UMBERTO ECO, FOUCAULT’S PENDULUM (William Weaver trans., UMBERTO ECO, THE ISLAND OF THE DAY BEFORE (William Weaver trans., UMBERTO ECO, THE NAME OF THE ROSE (William Weaver trans., 1983 ).

    Google Scholar 

  21. PAUL THAGARD, COMPUTATIONAL PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  22. WIGMORE, supra note 7, at 52–53.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Eco & SEBEOK, supra note 12, at 198–220.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See id. at 5.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See id. at 210–12.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Thomas A. Sebeok & Jean Umiker-Sebeok, “You Know My Method”: A Juxtaposition of Charles S. Peirce and Sherlock Holmes, in id. at 11–54.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See RESCHER, supra note 13, at 41–91.

    Google Scholar 

  28. THAGARD, supra note 20, at 52–65.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See G.A. SHAFER, MATHEMATICAL THEORY OF EVIDENCE 115–25 (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  30. THAGARD, supra note 20, at 58.

    Google Scholar 

  31. ANDERSON & TWINING, supra note 2, at 448.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Id. at 165–66.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See WIGMORE, supra note 7, at 858–81.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See JOSEPH B. KADANE & DAVID A. SCHUM, A PROBABILISTIC ANALYSIS OF THE SACCO AND VANZETTI EVIDENCE (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  35. See Eco & SEBEOK, supra note 12, at 206.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See Schum, supra note 3.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See Peter Tillers & David A. Schum, A Theory of Preliminary Fact Investigation, 24 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 931–1012 (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  38. See KADANE & SCHUM, supra note 34.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See WIGMORE, supra note 7, at 8.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See JOSEPHSON & JOSEPHSON, supra note 14, at 9.

    Google Scholar 

  41. See, e.g., M. MITCHELL WALDROP, COMPLEXITY: THE EMERGING SCIENCE AT THE EDGE OF ORDER AND CHAOS (1992).

    Google Scholar 

  42. PETER COVENEY & ROGER HIGHFIELD, FRONTIERS OF COMPLEXITY: THE SEARCH FOR ORDER IN A CHAOTIC WORLD 279 (1995).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Physica-Verlag Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schum, D.A. (2002). Species of Abductive Reasoning in Fact Investigation in Law. In: MacCrimmon, M., Tillers, P. (eds) The Dynamics of Judicial Proof. Studies in Fuzziness and Soft Computing, vol 94. Physica, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-7908-1792-8_16

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-7908-1792-8_16

  • Publisher Name: Physica, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-00323-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-7908-1792-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics