Advertisement

The Unity of Consciousness

  • Moritz Schlick
Part of the LEP Library of Exact Philosophy book series (LEP, volume 11)

Abstract

Is there, despite everything, a way out of doubt? Is there perhaps some assurance that the presupposition we have acknowledged as necessary is actually fulfilled? It would be vain to hope for any “proof” of this; proofs would only offer new points for radical skepticism to attack. No. The only thing that can help us is to present something that is exempt in advance from any doubt, that is, a fact. If there is such a fact, then the skepticism that put us on its track was not fruitless; it will have served to bring to light certain basic data of consciousness whose immeasurable significance might otherwise not have been correctly recognized and turned to account.

Keywords

Momentary Part Radical Skepticism Momentary Content Supreme Principle Synthetic Unity 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 18.
    E. Becher, Naturphilosophie, p. 108 (Kultur der Gegenwart, Part III, Division 7, Volume I, 1914).Google Scholar
  2. 19.
    A Treatise of Human Nature, Book I, Part IV, Section VI.Google Scholar
  3. 20.
    Here we disregard the question as to whether it is at all possible to define a “same” point of time for different consciousnesses.Google Scholar
  4. 21.
    I am happy to say that these statements, as well as some of the developments that follow respecting the same problem, although independent in conception, agree with ideas expressed by H. Cornelius in his Einleitung in die Philosophie, 2nd edition, 1911, § 23.Google Scholar
  5. 22.
    Wundt also remarks that a momentary consciousness would have to be called an “unconscious” one. See his System der Philosophie, 8th edition, Vol. II, 1907, p. 147.Google Scholar
  6. 23.
    Treatise of Human Nature, Book I, Part IV, Section VI.Google Scholar
  7. 24.
    For example, see T. Ribot, Les Maladies de la personalité, 1901.Google Scholar
  8. 25.
    H. Taine, Théorie de l’intelligence, 4th edition, Volume II, Appendix.Google Scholar
  9. 26.
    See too H. Cornelius, Einleitung in die Philosophie, 2nd edition, p. 231;Google Scholar
  10. 26a.
    F. Schumann, Zeitschrift für Psychologie, Vol. 17, pp. 127 ff.;Google Scholar
  11. 26b.
    William James, Psychologie (translated into German by M. Dürr), pp. 280 ff.Google Scholar
  12. 27.
    Hans Cornelius’ book Transzendentale Systematik (Munich 1916) seeks to take the thought seriously, but misses its goal. It overshoots the mark in attempting to derive all possible knowledge, even the necessity of Euclidean geometry, from the unity of personal consciousness.Google Scholar
  13. 28.
    For example, H. Driesch (Philosophie des Organischen, II, pp. 380 ff.) regards “the unity of subjective experience in general and memory in particular” as one of the “three windows” through which we gaze into the absolute.Google Scholar
  14. 29.
    Essay Concerning the Human Understanding, Book 4, Chapter 1, § 4.Google Scholar
  15. 30.
    Loc. cit. Google Scholar
  16. 31.
    John Stuart Mill, Logic, Book I, Chapter V, § 5, note.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag/Wien 1974

Authors and Affiliations

  • Moritz Schlick

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations