Advertisement

Pragmatik pp 103-127 | Cite as

Enrichment and Loosening: Complementary Processes in Deriving the Proposition Expressed?

  • Robyn Carston
Chapter
Part of the Linguistische Berichte book series (LINGB)

Abstract

One important consequence of the relevance-theoretic view of cognition and communication is the following: we can think many thoughts that our language cannot encode, and we can communicate many thoughts that our utterances do not encode. Strictly speaking, virtually no sentence encodes a complete thought; certain processes of contextual filling-in are required before anything of a propositional nature emerges at all. However, that more basic point is not my primary concern in this short paper. The idea is that, even given such processes of propositional completion, a great many of our thoughts are of a much finer grain than that of the minimal propositions which result from these processes. It follows that there are many more concepts (construed as constituents of thoughts) than there are words in the language.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Atlas, J. (1992): “Why ‘three’ doesn’t mean 3”. Unpublished ms.Google Scholar
  2. Bach, K. (1994a): “Semantic slack: What is said and more”. In: S. Tsohatzidis, ed.: Foundations of Speech Act Theory: Philosophical and Linguistic Perspectives. London and New York: Rout-ledge, 267–291.Google Scholar
  3. Bach, K. (1994b): “Conversational impliciture”. Mind and Language 9, 124–162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Carston, R. (1988): “Implicature, explicature and truth-theoretic semantics”. In: R. Kempson, ed.: Mental Representations: The Interface between Language and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 155–181. Reprinted in 1991 in: S. Davis, ed.: Pragmatics: A Reader. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 33–51.Google Scholar
  5. Carston, R. (1990): “Quantity maxims and generalised implicature”. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 2, 1–31. Revised version in 1995 in Lingua 96, 213–244.Google Scholar
  6. Carston, R. (1993): “Conjunction, explanation and relevance”. Lingua 90, 27–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Carston, R. (1996): “Metalinguistic negation and echoic use”. Journal of Pragmatics 25, 309–330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dogan, G. (1992): “The pragmatics of indeterminacy and indirectness of meaning: a relevance-theo-retic approach to epigrams and graffiti in Turkish”. PhD thesis, University of Manchester.Google Scholar
  9. Flieger, J. (1996): “Metaphor and categorization”. Seminar paper, Linguistics Dept., School of Oriental and African Studies, London.Google Scholar
  10. Gibbs, R. & J. Moise (1997): “Pragmatics in understanding what is said”. Cognition 62, 51–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Grice, H.P. (1978): Further notes on logic and conversation. Syntax and Semantics 9: Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, 113–127.Google Scholar
  12. Horn, L. (1985): “Metalinguistic negation and pragmatic ambiguity”. Language 61, 121–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Horn, L. (1989): A Natural History of Negation. Cicago: University of Chicago Press. Ifantidou, E. (1994): “Parentheticals and relevance”. PhD thesis, University College London.Google Scholar
  14. Papafragou, A. (1995): “Metonymy and relevance”. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 7, 141–175.Google Scholar
  15. Papafragou, A. (1996): “Figurative language and the semantics/ pragmatics interface”. Language and Literature.Google Scholar
  16. Reboul, A. (1989): “Relevance and argumentation: how bald can you get?” Argumentation 3, 285302.Google Scholar
  17. Récanati, F. (1993): “Truth-conditional pragmatics”. In: F. Récanati: Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. Oxford: Blackwell, 233–254.Google Scholar
  18. Récanati, F. (1995): “The alleged priority of literal meaning”. Cognitive Science 19, 207–232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Rouchota, V. (1992): “On the referential/attributive distinction”. Lingua 87, 137–167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Sperber, D. (1989): “Concepts and fuzziness”. Talk at the Relevance Theory Workshop, Essex.Google Scholar
  21. Sperber, D. & D. Wilson, (1985/86): “Loose talk”. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society LXXXVI, 153–171.Google Scholar
  22. Sperber, D. & D. Wilson, (1986): Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  23. Sperber, D. & D. Wilson, (1995): Relevance: Communication and Cognition, Second Edition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  24. Sperber, D. & D. Wilson, (forthcoming): Relevance and Meaning. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  25. Strawson, P. (1974): Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
  26. Wilson, D. (1993/94): Philosophy of Language lectures. Ms, University College London.Google Scholar
  27. Wilson, D. (1995): “Is there a maxim of truthfulness?”. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 7, 197–212.Google Scholar
  28. Wilson, D. & D. Sperber, (1981): “On Grice’s theory of conversation”. In: P. Werth, ed.: Conversation and Discourse. London: Croom Helm, 155–179.Google Scholar
  29. Wilson, D. & D. Sperber, (1993): “Pragmatics and time”. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 5, 277–298.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden 1997

Authors and Affiliations

  • Robyn Carston
    • 1
  1. 1.LondonUK

Personalised recommendations