Skip to main content

Deontic Conflicts and Multiple Violations

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Book cover Logic, Language, and Computation (TbiLLC 2013)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 8984))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 716 Accesses

Abstract

This paper presents a novel semantics for deontic modals which provides a uniform solution to prominent puzzles in the literature. The paper focuses on deontic conflicts, discussing them using the Dr. Procrastinate puzzle as an example. The focus lies on the Dr. Procrastinate puzzle as it combines an upward monotonicity puzzle with a conflict of obligations, allowing an explanation of the solutions to both types of puzzle in detail.

The semantics is an extension of radical inquisitive semantics, and it modifies Andersonian deontic modals as it introduces quantification over alternatives. The solution to deontic conflicts is made possible by the semantics allowing permission and prohibition statements to introduce multiple violations. Each rule is assigned a different violation, allowing for reasoning with rules also in cases where it is impossible to avoid violating all rules.

I am grateful to Jeroen Groenendijk, Stefan Hinterwimmer, Floris Roelofsen, Mandy Simons, Carla Umbach, and Matthijs Westera for extensive discussion of the ideas presented here and closely related topics, to two anonymous reviewers for constructive criticism, and to the Estonian Research Council for their support.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    May and must can also receive, among others, epistemic readings. For a related treatment of epistemic modals, see [2].

  2. 2.

    This simple version of a deontic conflict does not pose a problem for Kratzer semantics which also considers an ordering of worlds. See for example Lassiter [25, p. 151] for discussion on deontic conflicts which also cause problems for Kratzer semantics.

  3. 3.

    See [19].

  4. 4.

    See [27].

  5. 5.

    See [20, 30].

  6. 6.

    See [19].

  7. 7.

    In this paper, ought is used interchangeably with must because distinctions between the two do not play a role in the presented treatment.

  8. 8.

    Based on Aher [1, 3, 4].

  9. 9.

    Anderson introduced relevant implication instead of material implication, but a full discussion of this logic is outside of the scope of this paper.

  10. 10.

    The image is taken from the popular online chess site chess.com.

  11. 11.

    A reviewer pointed out that there’s an alternative construal put forward by Frank [18], Kaufmann and Schwager [21] and Cariani, Kaufmann and Kaufmann [12] among others in which there’s always a covert epistemic necessity operator over the consequent of a conditional.

  12. 12.

    The treatment of conditionals will necessarily be brief. The radical framework, developed by Sano [28] and Groenendijk & Roelofsen [16], provides an intuitive basis for this treatment of deontic modals. The details of a suppositional extension can be found in [17].

  13. 13.

    We are constrained to deontic modals. See work in progress on suppositional inquisitive semantics [2] on how to treat epistemic modals in a structurally similar manner.

  14. 14.

    There is a further extension of the system [17] which distinguishes a third relation between states and sentences which concerns a state dismissing a supposition of a sentence. In the semantics presented here, when a state rejects \(p\), it both supports and rejects \(p \rightarrow q\), and \(\Diamond p\). In the suppositional extension such states are characterized as neither supporting nor rejecting them, but as dismissing a supposition of theirs.

  15. 15.

    Equivalence is defined as mutual entailment.

  16. 16.

    The natural language examples are for illustration only. The actual picture of positive and negative responses is naturally more complicated. See for example Brasoveanu et al. [10].

  17. 17.

    If you are reading this in gray-scale, violation worlds are darker and non-violation worlds are lighter.

  18. 18.

    SML treats permission as weaker, so

    figure w

    does not guarantee that when you bring about \(p\), no violation occurs.

  19. 19.

    A comparison of Figs. 9 and 16 also shows that \((p\vee q)\rightarrow r\) and \((p \wedge q)\rightarrow \lnot r\) are consistent with each other. This is also the case in Kratzer semantics if it’s combined with an alternative-based treatment of disjunction. See for example Alonso-Ovalle [6].

  20. 20.

    See [4], especially for discussion on how to also attain disjunctive readings under permission.

  21. 21.

    Stronger is understood through entailment:

    figure al

    .

  22. 22.

    Strengthening the antecedent also doesn’t hold for obligation for the same reason as it does not hold for implication and permission, but we do not have the space to go through the calculations here.

  23. 23.

    This example is a simplification of a World Trade Organization panel report from case DSU 344. For further details see [4, p. 104].

  24. 24.

    This is not to say that further work should not focus on more fine-grained conceptualizations.

  25. 25.

    Such an approach is not to be confused with work on presuppositions which, as far as the author is aware, is an entirely disconnected phenomenon.

  26. 26.

    See [2].

  27. 27.

    More involved scenarios will likely require a more fine-grained approach which compares violations.

References

  1. Aher, M.: Deontic contexts and the interpretation of disjunction in legal discourse. Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue Canadienne de Linguistique 58(1), 13–42 (2013). http://bit.ly/15FfFdB

    Google Scholar 

  2. Aher, M., Groenendijk, J.A.G.: Searching for directions: epistemic and deontic modals in InqS. Presented at the Tenth International Tbilisi Symposium on Language, Logic and Computation (TbiLLC), 26 September 2013 (2014). http://bit.ly/1pA0kin

  3. Aher, M.: Free Choice in Deontic Inquisitive Semantics (DIS). In: Aloni, M., Kimmelman, V., Roelofsen, F., Sassoon, G.W., Schulz, K., Westera, M. (eds.) Logic, Language and Meaning. LNCS, vol. 7218, pp. 22–31. Springer, Heidelberg (2012). http://bit.ly/UzirsR

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  4. Aher, M.: Modals in legal language. Ph.D. thesis, University of Osnabrück (2013). http://bit.ly/1ca9Ru4

  5. Aloni, M.: Free choice, modals, and imperatives. Nat. Lang. Semant. 15, 65–94 (2007). http://bit.ly/Zdh8k9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Alonso-Ovalle, L.: Disjunction in alternative semantics. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Anderson, A.R.: Some nasty problems in the formal logic of ethics. Nous 1, 345–360 (1967). http://bit.ly/NcSlZG

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Asher, N., Bonevac, D.: Free choice permission is strong permission. Synthese 145(3), 303–323 (2005). http://bit.ly/RswjTm

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Barker, C.: Free choice permission as resource-sensitive reasoning. Semant. Pragmat. 3, 1–38 (2010). http://bit.ly/16goZPL

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Brasoveanu, A., Farkas, D., Roelofsen, F.: N-words and sentential negation: evidence from polarity particles and VP ellipsis. Semant. Pragmat. 6, 1–33 (2013). http://bit.ly/11wY2e0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Cariani, F.: Ought and resolution semantics. Noûs (2011). doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2011.00839.x. http://bit.ly/LRCsJQ

  12. Cariani, F., Kaufmann, M., Kaufmann, S.: Deliberative modality under epistemic uncertainty. Linguist. Philos. 36(3), 225–259 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Ciardelli, I., Groenendijk, J.A.G., Roelofsen, F.: Inquisitive Semantics: NASSLLI 2012 lecture notes (2012) Unpublished manuscript. http://bit.ly/V6uWy6

  14. Ciardelli, I., Roelofsen, F.: Inquisitive logic. J. Philos. Log. 40(1), 55–94 (2011). http://bit.ly/NlCcRF

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Groenendijk, J.A.G., Roelofsen, F.: Inquisitive Semantics and Pragmatics. Presented at the Stanford workshop on Language, Communication and Rational Agency, 30–31 May 2009. http://bit.ly/MoWgAx

  16. Groenendijk, J.A.G., Roelofsen, F.: Radical Inquisitive Semantics. presented first at Osnabrueck University Institute of Cognitive Science Colloquium on the 13th of January 2010. Unpublished http://bit.ly/NFO9zn

  17. Groenendijk, J.A.G., Roelofsen, F.: Suppositional Inquisitive Semantics. In: Proceedings of the Tenth International Tbilisi Symposium on Language, Logic and Computation (2014). Submitted

    Google Scholar 

  18. Frank, A.: Context dependence in modal constructions. Ph.D. thesis, University of Stuttgart (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Jackson, F.: On the semantics and logic of obligation. Mind, New Series 94(374), 177–195 (1985). http://bit.ly/OQSwx9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Kamp, H.: Free choice permission. In: Aristotelian Society Proceedings N.S 74, pp. 57–74 (1973). http://bit.ly/Rb1cxb

  21. Kaufmann, S., Schwager, M.: A unified analysis of conditional imperatives. In: Cormany, E., Ito, S., Lutz, D. (eds.) Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory(SALT), vol. 19, pp. 239–259 (2011). eLanguage

    Google Scholar 

  22. Kratzer, A.: Conditional necessity and possibility. In: Bäuerle, R., Egli, U., von Stechow, A. (eds.) Semantics from Different Points of View, vol. 6, pp. 117–147. Springer, Heidelberg (1979)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  23. Kratzer, A.: Modals and Conditionals: New and Revised Perspectives. Oxford studies in Theoretical Linguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Kratzer, A.: What “Must" and “Can" must and can mean. Linguist. Philos. 1, 337–355 (1977). http://bit.ly/ZhvZtR

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Lassiter, D.: Measurement and modality: the scalar basis of modal semantics. Ph.D Dissertation, Department of Linguistics, New York University (2011). http://bit.ly/OYyCji

  26. Lewis, D.: Counterfactuals. Basil Blackwell, Oxford (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ross, A.: Imperatives and logic. Theoria 7, 53–71 (1941). Reprinted in Philosophy of Science 11(1), 30–46 (1944). http://bit.ly/QPYk73

    Google Scholar 

  28. Sano, K.: A Note on Support and Rejection for Radical Inquisitive Semantics (2010). Unpublished manuscript

    Google Scholar 

  29. von Wright, G.H.: Deontic logic. Mind, New Series 60(237), 1–15 (1951)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Zimmermann, T.E.: Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Nat. Lang. Seman. 8, 255–290 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Aher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this paper

Cite this paper

Aher, M. (2015). Deontic Conflicts and Multiple Violations. In: Aher, M., Hole, D., Jeřábek, E., Kupke, C. (eds) Logic, Language, and Computation. TbiLLC 2013. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 8984. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-46906-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-46906-4_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-46905-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-46906-4

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics