Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in Choice and Welfare ((WELFARE))

  • 844 Accesses

Abstract

The enlightenment was a philosophical project to construct a rational society without the need for a supreme being. It opened the way for the creation of market democracy and rapid economic growth. At the same time economic growth is the underlying cause of climate change, and we have become aware that this may destroy our civilization. The principal underpinning of the enlightenment project is the general equilibrium theorem (GET) of Arrow and Debreu (Econometrica 22:265–290, 1954), asserting the existence of a Pareto optimal price equilibrium. Arrow’s work in social choice can be interpreted as an attempt to construct a more general social equilibrium theorem. The current paper surveys recent results in social choice which suggests that chaos rather than equilibrium is generic.We also consider models of belief aggregation similar to Condorcet’s Jury theorem and mention Penn’s Theorem on existence of a belief equilibrium.However, it is suggested that a belief equilibrium with regard to the appropriate response to climate change depends on the creation of a fundamental social principle of “guardianship of our planetary home.” It is suggested that this will involve conflict between entrenched economic interests and ordinary people, as the effects of climate change make themselves felt in many countries.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Pagden [149] for an argument about the significance today of the enlightenment project, but a counter argument by Gray [7981].

  2. 2.

    Weber (1904) speculated that there was a connection between the values of Protestantism and Capitalism. It may be that there are connections between the preference for scientific explanation and protestant belief about the relationship between God and humankind.

  3. 3.

    See Feingold (2004).

  4. 4.

    For Hobbes, see Rogow (1986). For Descartes, see Gaukroger (1995). For Spinoza and Liebnitz see Stewart (2006) and Goldstein (2006). See also Israel (2012) for the development of the Radical Enlightenment.

  5. 5.

    It is of interest that the English word “soul” derives from Old English sáwol (first used in the eighth century poem, Beowulf ).

  6. 6.

    Hawking and Mlodinow (2010) assert that God did not create the Universe, perhaps implying that the soul does not exist. However they do say that they understand Isaac Newton’s belief that God did “create” and “conserve” order in the universe. See other books by Dawkins [55] (2008) and Hitchens (2007) on the same theme, as well as Wright (2009) on the evolution of the notion of God.

  7. 7.

    See for example Hardin [87, 88], Taylor [215, 216], Axelrod and Hamilton [12], Axelrod [12, 13], Kreps et al. [109], Margolis [122].

  8. 8.

    Strong reciprocity means the punishment of those who do not cooperate.

  9. 9.

    Indeed, White et al. (2009) present evidence of a high degree of cooperation among very early hominids dating back about 4MYBP (million years before the present). The evidence includes anatomical data which allows for inferences about the behavioral characteristics of these early hominids.

  10. 10.

    Gintis cites the work of Robson and Kaplan (2003) who use an economic model to estimate the correlation between brain size and life expectancy (a measure of efficiency). In this context, the increase in brain size is driven by the requirement to solve complex cooperative games against nature.

  11. 11.

    See the discussion in [192].

  12. 12.

    Weitzman [225] and Chichilnisky [47]. See also Chichilnisky and Eisenberger [47] on other catastrophic events such as collision with an asteroid.

  13. 13.

    See Schofield [172, 175, 176]. In a sense these voting theorems can be regarded as derivative of Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem [8]. See also Arrow [9].

  14. 14.

    The theory of chaos or complexity is rooted in Smale’s fundamental theorem [198] that structural stability of dynamical systems is not “generic” or typical whenever the state space has more than two dimensions.

  15. 15.

    In their early analysis of chaos, Li and Yorke [115] showed that in the domain of a chaotic transformation f it was possible for almost any pair of positions (x, y) to transition from x to y = f r(x), where f r means the r times reiteration of f. 

  16. 16.

    See Minsky [135, 136] and Keynes’s earlier work in 1921.

  17. 17.

    Karklins and Petersen [99] and Lohmann [116]. See also Bikhchandani et al. [23].

  18. 18.

    The response by the citizens of these countries to the demise of Osama bin Laden on May 2, 2011, is in large degree also unpredictable.

  19. 19.

    See for example Carothers [33] and Collier [50].

  20. 20.

    Golub and Jackson [76].

  21. 21.

    See Henrich et al. [90, 91], which reports on experiments in fifteen “small-scale societies,” using the game theoretic tools of the “prisoners’ dilemma,” the “ultimatum game,” etc.

  22. 22.

    See also Acemoglu and Robinson [3].

  23. 23.

    The popular protests in N.Africa and the Middle East in 2011 were in opposition to oligarchic and autocratic power.

  24. 24.

    See also Shafer and Sonnenschein [195] who use this result to extend the Arrow Debreu equilibrium existence theorem [10].

  25. 25.

    ie d(x)(v) > 0 for all x ∈ V, for all v ∈ H(x), whenever \(H(x)\neq \varnothing.\)

  26. 26.

    Results on belief aggregation include [153] and [127].

  27. 27.

    Schofield [169, 170], Ladha [111113], Ladha and Miller [113].

  28. 28.

    Sunstein [209, 211] also notes that belief aggregation can lead to a situation where subgroups in the society come to hold very disparate opinions.

  29. 29.

    Gleick [73], Buchanan [29, 30], Gladwell [72], Johnson [97], Barabasi [17, 18], Strogatz [205], Watts [222, 223], Surowiecki [212], Ball [15], Christakis and Fowler [49]

  30. 30.

    See, for example, Mandelbrot and Hudson [121], Shiller [196, 197], Taleb [213], Barbera [19], Cassidy [35], Fox [67].

  31. 31.

    See for example Cavallli-Sforza and Feldman [37], Bowles et al. [25].

  32. 32.

    See also Eldredge [60] and Gould (1976).

  33. 33.

    Indeed as I understand the dynamical models, the chaotic episodes are due to the complex interactions of dynamical processes in the oceans, on the land, in weather, and in the heavens. These are very like interlinked coalitions of non-gradient vector fields.

  34. 34.

    This is suggested by Kahneman [98].

  35. 35.

    As Smolin [203] points out, the anthropic principle has been adopted because of the experimental evidence that the expansion of the universe is accelerating. Indeed it has led to the hypothesis that there is an infinity of universes all with different laws. An alternative inference is the principle of intelligent design. My own inference is that we require a teleology as proposed in the conclusion.

  36. 36.

    The work by Poincare in the late nineteenth century focussed on the structural stability of the solar system and was the first to conceive of the notion of chaos.

  37. 37.

    Zhang et al. [230] and Hsiang et al. [96] have provided quantitative analyses of such adverse effects in the past. See also Parker [152] for an historical account of the effect of climate change in early modern Europe.

  38. 38.

    See Sperber [202] for a discussion of the development of Marx’s ideas, in the context of nineteenth century belief in the teleology of “progresś” or the advance of civilization. The last 100 years has however,made it difficult to hold such beliefs.

  39. 39.

    The philosopher [141] argues that without a teleogy of some kind, we are left with Darwinian evolutionary theory, which by itself cannot provide a full explanation of what we are and where we are going. See also [217] and [20].

References

  1. Acemoglu D (2008) Oligarchic versus democratic societies. J Eur Econ Assoc 6:1–44

    Google Scholar 

  2. Acemoglu D, Robinson J (2006) Economic origins of dictatorship and democracy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  3. Acemoglu D, Robinson J (2008) Persistence of power, elites, and institutions. Am Econ Rev 98:267–293

    Google Scholar 

  4. Acemoglu D, Robinson J (2011) Why nations fail. Profile Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  5. Acemoglu D, Johnson S, Robinson J, Yared P (2009) Reevaluating the modernization hypothesis. J Monet Econ 56:1043–1058

    Google Scholar 

  6. Acemoglu D, Ozdaglar A, Tahbaz-Salehi A (2010) Cascades in networks and aggregate volatility. NBER working paper # 16516

    Google Scholar 

  7. Akerlof GA, Shiller RJ (2009) Animal spirits. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  8. Arrow KJ (1951) Social choice and individual values. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  9. Arrow K (1986) Rationality of self and others in an economic system. J Bus 59:S385–S399

    Google Scholar 

  10. Arrow K, Debreu G (1954) Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Econometrica 22:265–290

    Google Scholar 

  11. Austen-Smith D, Banks J (1996) Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet Jury theorem. Am Polit Sci Rev 90:34–45

    Google Scholar 

  12. Axelrod R (1981) The emergence of cooperation among egoists. Am Polit Sci Rev 75:306–318

    Google Scholar 

  13. Axelrod R (1984) The evolution of cooperation. Basic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  14. Bak P, Sneppen (1993) Punctuated equilibrium and criticality in a simple model of evolution. Phys Rev Lett 71(24):4083–4086

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ball P (2004) Critical mass. Ferrar, Strauss and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  16. Banks JS (1995) Singularity theory and core existence in the spatial model. J Math Econ 24:523–536

    Google Scholar 

  17. Barabasi A-L (2003) Linked. Plume, New York

    Google Scholar 

  18. Barabasi A-L (2010) Bursts. Dutton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  19. Barbera R (2009) The cost of capitalism: understanding market mayhem. McGraw Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  20. Bellah (2011) Religion in human evolution. Belknap, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  21. Bergstrom T (1975) The existence of maximal elements and equilibria in the absence of transitivity. University of Michigan, Typescript

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bergstrom T (1992) When non-transitive relations take maxima and competitive equilibrium can’t be beat. In: Neuefeind W, Riezman R (eds) Economic theory and international trade. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  23. Bikhchandani S, Hirschleifer D, Welsh I (1992) A theory of fads, fashion, custom, and cultural change as information cascades. J Polit Econ 100:992–1026

    Google Scholar 

  24. Binmore K (2005) Natural justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  25. Bowles S et al (2003) The co-evolution of individual behaviors and socal institutions. J Theor Biol 223:135–147

    Google Scholar 

  26. Boyd J, Richerson PJ (2005) The origin and evolution of culture. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  27. Brown R (1971) The Lefschetz fixed point theorem. Scott and Foreman, Glenview, IL

    Google Scholar 

  28. Brouwer LEJ (1912) Uber abbildung von mannigfaltikeiten. Math Analen 71:97–115

    Google Scholar 

  29. Buchanan M (2001) Ubiquity. Crown, New York

    Google Scholar 

  30. Buchanan M (2003) Nexus. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  31. Burkhart JM, Hrdy SB, van Schaik CP (2009) Cooperative breeding and human cognitive evolution. Evol Anthropol 18:175–186

    Google Scholar 

  32. Calvin WH (2003) The ascent of mind. Bantam, New York

    Google Scholar 

  33. Carothers T (2002) The end of the transition paradigm. J Democr 13:5–21

    Google Scholar 

  34. Caryl (2011) Strange Rebels 1979 and the birth of the 20th century Basic Books. New York

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cassidy J (2009) How markets fail: the logic of economic calamities. Farrar, Strauss and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  36. Casti J (2010) Mood matters Copernicus. New York

    Google Scholar 

  37. Cavallli-Sforza L, Feldman M (1981) Cultural transmission and evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  38. Chichilnisky G (1992) Social diversity, arbitrage, and gains from trade: a unified perspective on resource allocation. Am Econ Rev 84:427–434

    Google Scholar 

  39. Chichilnisky G (1993) Intersecting families of sets and the topology of cones in economics. Bull Am Math Soc 29:189–207

    Google Scholar 

  40. Chichilnisky G (1995) Limited arbitrage is necessary and sufficient for the existence of a competitive equilibrium with or without short sales. Econ Theory 5:79–107

    Google Scholar 

  41. Chichilnisky G (1996) Markets and games: a simple equivalence among the core, equilibrium and limited arbitrage. Metroeconomica 47:266–280

    Google Scholar 

  42. Chichilnisky G (1997) A topological invariant for competitive markets. J Math Econ 28:445–469

    Google Scholar 

  43. Chichilnisky G (1997) Limited arbitrage is necessary and sufficient for the existence of a equilibrium. J Math Econ 28:470–479

    Google Scholar 

  44. Chichilnisky G (1997) Market arbitrage, social choice and the core. Soc Choice Welf 14:161–198

    Google Scholar 

  45. Chichilnisky G (2009) The topology of fear. J Math Econ 45:807–816

    Google Scholar 

  46. Chichilnisky G (2009) Avoiding extinction: equal treatment of the present and the future. Working Paper: Columbia University

    Google Scholar 

  47. Chichilinsky G (2010) The foundations of statistics with black swans. Math Soc Sci 59:184–192

    Google Scholar 

  48. Chichilinsky G (2012) Sustainable markets with short sales. Econ Theory 49:293–307

    Google Scholar 

  49. Christakis N, Fowler JH (2011) Connected. Back Bay, New York

    Google Scholar 

  50. Collier P (2009) Wars, guns and votes. Harper, New York

    Google Scholar 

  51. Collier P (2010) The plundered planet. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  52. Condorcet N (1994 [1785]) Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. Imprimerie Royale, Paris. Translated in part in: McLean I, Hewitt F (eds) Condorcet: foundations of social choice and political theory. Edward Elgar Publishing, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  53. Corcos et al (2002) Imitation and contrarian behavior: hyperbolic bubbles, crashes and chaos. Quant Finan 2:264–281

    Google Scholar 

  54. Dasgupta P (2005) Three conceptions of intergenerational Justice. In: Lillehammer H, Mellor DH (eds) Ramsey’s legacy. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  55. Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  56. Debreu G (1970) Economies with a finite number of equilibria. Econometrica 38:387–392

    Google Scholar 

  57. Debreu G (1976) The application to economics of differential topology and global analysis: regular differentiable economies. Am Econ Rev 66:280–287

    Google Scholar 

  58. Deutscher G (2006) The unfolding of language. Holt, New York

    Google Scholar 

  59. Easley D, Kleinberg J (2010) Networks, crowds and markets. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  60. Eldredge N (1976) Differential evolutionary rates. Paleobiology 2:174–177

    Google Scholar 

  61. Eldridge N, Gould SJ (1972) Punctuated equilibrium. In: Schopf T (ed) Models of paleobiology. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  62. Fan K (1961) A generalization of Tychonoff’s fixed point theorem. Math Ann 42:305–310

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ferguson N (2002) Empire: the rise and demise of the British world order. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  64. Ferguson N (2011) Civilization. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  65. Feingold M (2004) The Newtonian moment. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  66. Flyvbjerg H, Sneppen K, Bak P (1993) A mean field theory for a simple model of evolution. Phys Rev Lett 71:4087–4090

    Google Scholar 

  67. Fox J (2009) The myth of the rational market. Harper, New York

    Google Scholar 

  68. Fukuyama F (2011) The origins of political order. Ferrar, Strauss and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  69. Gaukroger S (1995) Descartes. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  70. Gazzaniger M S (2008) Human Harper. New York

    Google Scholar 

  71. Gintis H (2000) Strong reciprocity and human sociality. J Theor Biol 206:169–179

    Google Scholar 

  72. Gladwell M (2002) The tipping point. Back Bay, New York

    Google Scholar 

  73. Gleick J (1987) Chaos: making a new science. Viking, New York

    Google Scholar 

  74. Gödel K (1931) Uber formal unentscheidbare Satze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme. Monatschefte fur Mathematik und Physik 38:173–98. Translated as On formally undecidable propositions of Principia Mathematica and related systems. In: van Heijenoort J (ed) Frege and G ödel: Two Fundamental Texts in Mathematical Logic. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  75. Goldstein R (2006) Betraying Spinoza. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  76. Golub B, Jackson M (2010) Naive learning in social networks and the wisdom of crowds. Am Econ J 2:112–149

    Google Scholar 

  77. Gould SJ (1976) Full House. Belknap, New York

    Google Scholar 

  78. Gore A (2006) The Future Random. New York

    Google Scholar 

  79. Gray J (1995) Enlightenment’s wake. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  80. Gray J (1997) Endgames. Blackwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  81. Gray J (2000) False dawn. New Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  82. Gribbin J (2011) Alone in the universe. Wiley, NewYork

    Google Scholar 

  83. Hahn F (1973) On the notion of equilibrium in economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Hamilton W (1964) The genetical evolution of social behavior I and II. J Theor Biol 7:1–52

    Google Scholar 

  85. Hamilton W (1970) Selfish and spiteful behavior in an evolutionary model. Nature 228:1218–1220

    Google Scholar 

  86. Hardin G (1968 [1973]) The tragedy of the commons. In: Daly HE (ed) Towards a steady state economy. Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  87. Hardin R (1971) Collective action as an agreeable prisons’ dilemma. Behav Sci 16:472–481

    Google Scholar 

  88. Hardin R (1982) Collective action. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD

    Google Scholar 

  89. Hawking S, Mlodinow L (2010) The Grand Design. Random House New York

    Google Scholar 

  90. Henrich J et al (2004) Foundations of human sociality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  91. Henrich J et al (2005) Economic man’ in cross-cultural perspective: behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies. Behav Brain Sci 28:795–855

    Google Scholar 

  92. Hirsch M (1976) Differential topology. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  93. Hitchens C (2007) God is not great. Hachette, New york

    Google Scholar 

  94. Hobbes T (2009 [1651]) In: Gaskin (ed) Leviathan; or the matter, forme, and power of a common-wealth, ecclesiastical and civil. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  95. Hrdy SB (2011) Mothers and others: the evolutionary origins of mutual understanding. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  96. Hsiang S et al (2013) Quantifying the influence of climate on human conflict. Sci Express 10:1126

    Google Scholar 

  97. Johnson S (2002) Emergence. Scribner, New York

    Google Scholar 

  98. Kahneman D (2011) Thinking fast and slow. Ferrar Strauss and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  99. Karklins R, Petersen R (1993) Decision calculus of protestors and regime change: Eastern Europe 1989. J Polit 55:588–614

    Google Scholar 

  100. Kauffman S (1993) The origins of order. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  101. Keohane R (1984) After hegemony. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  102. Keohane R, Nye R (1977) Power and interdependence. Little Brown, New York

    Google Scholar 

  103. Keynes JM (1921) Treatise on probability. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  104. Keynes JM (1936) The general theory of employment, interest and money. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  105. Kindleberger C (1973) The world in depression 1929–1939. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA

    Google Scholar 

  106. Knaster B, Kuratowski K, Mazurkiewicz S (1929) Ein beweis des fixpunktsatzes fur n-dimensionale simplexe. Fund Math 14:132–137

    Google Scholar 

  107. Konishi M (1996) Equilibrium in an abstract political economy. Social Choice and Welf 13:43–50

    Google Scholar 

  108. Kramer GH (1973) On a class of equilibrium conditions for majority rule. Econometrica 41:285–297

    Google Scholar 

  109. Kreps DM et al (1982) Rational cooperation in the finitely repeated prisoners’ dilemma. J Econ Theory 27:245–252

    Google Scholar 

  110. Kurz M, Motolese M (2001) Endogenous uncertainty and market volatility. Econ Theory 17:497–544

    Google Scholar 

  111. Ladha K (1992) Condorcet’s jury theorem, free speech and correlated votes. Am J Polit Sci 36:617–674

    Google Scholar 

  112. Ladha K (1993) Condorcet’s jury theorem in the light of de Finetti’s theorem: majority rule with correlated votes. Soc Choice Welf 10:69–86

    Google Scholar 

  113. Ladha K, Miller G (1996) Political discourse, factions and the general will: correlated voting and Condorcet’s jury theorem. In: Schofield N (ed) Collective decision making. Kluwer, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  114. Laplace PS (1951 [1814]) Essai Philosophique sur les Probabilités. Gauthiers-Villars, Paris. A philosophical essay on probabilities (Trans. F. Truscott and F. Emory ) Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  115. Li TY, Yorke JA (1975) Period three implies chaos. Math Mon 82:985–992

    Google Scholar 

  116. Lohmann S (1994) The dynamics of information cascades. World Polit 47:42–101

    Google Scholar 

  117. Lorenz EN (1962) The statistical prediction of solutions of dynamical equations. In: Proceedings of the international symposium om numerical weather prediction, Tokyo

    Google Scholar 

  118. Lorenz EN (1963) Deterministic non periodic flow. J Atmos Sci 20:130–141

    Google Scholar 

  119. Lorenz EN (1993) The essence of chaos. University of Washington Press, Seattle

    Google Scholar 

  120. Madison J (1999[1787]) Federalist X. In: Rakove J (ed) Madison: writings. Library Classics, New York

    Google Scholar 

  121. Mandelbrot B, Hudson R (2004) The (mis)behavior of markets. Perseus, New York

    Google Scholar 

  122. Margolis H (1982) Selfishness, altruism and rationality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  123. Margulis L, Sagan D (2002) Acquiring genomes. Basic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  124. Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  125. McKelvey RD (1976) Intransitivities in multidimensional voting models and some implications for agenda control. J Econ Theory 12:472–482

    Google Scholar 

  126. McKelvey RD (1979) General conditions for global intransitivities in formal voting models. Econometrica 47:1085–1112

    Google Scholar 

  127. McKelvey RD, Page T (1986) Common knowledge, consensus and affregrate information. Econometrica 54:109—127

    Google Scholar 

  128. McKelvey RD, Schofield N (1987) Generalized symmetry conditions at a core point. Econometrica 55:923–933

    Google Scholar 

  129. McWhorter J (2001) The power of babel. Holt, New York

    Google Scholar 

  130. Merton RC (1973) Theory of rational option pricing. Bell J Econ Manag Sci 4:141–183

    Google Scholar 

  131. Michael E (1956) Continuous selections I. Ann Math 63:361–382

    Google Scholar 

  132. Miller G, Schofield N (2003) Activists and partisan realignment in the U.S. Am Polit Sci Rev 97:245–260

    Google Scholar 

  133. Miller G, Schofield N (2008) The transformation of the Republican and Democratic party coalitions in the United States. Perspect Polit 6:433–450

    Google Scholar 

  134. Milnor JW (1997) Topology from a differential viewpoint. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  135. Minsky H (1975) John maynard keynes. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  136. Minsky H (1986) Stabilizing an unstable economy. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  137. Mokyr J (2005) The intellectual origins of modern economic growth. J Econ Hist 65:285–351

    Google Scholar 

  138. Mokyr J (2010) The enlightened economy: an economic history of Britain 1700–1850. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  139. Mokyr J, Nye VC (2007) Distributional coalitions, the Industrial Revolution, and the origins of economic growth in Britain. South Econ J 74:50–70

    Google Scholar 

  140. Morris I (2010) Why the west rules. Ferrar, Strauss and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  141. Nagel T (2012) Mind and cosmos. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  142. Nakamura K (1979) The vetoers in a simple game with ordinal preference. Int J Game Theory 8:55–61

    Google Scholar 

  143. North DC (1990) Institutions, institutional change and economic performance. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  144. North DC, Weingast BR (1989) Constitutions and commitment: the evolution of institutions governing public choice in seventeenth century England. J Econ Hist 49:803–832

    Google Scholar 

  145. North DC, Wallis B, Weingast BR (2009) Violence and social orders: a conceptual framework for interpreting recorded human history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  146. Nowak M (2011) Supercooperators. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  147. Ormerod P (2001) Butterfly economics. Basic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  148. Ostrom E (1990) Governing the commons. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  149. Pagden A (2013) The enlightenment. Random, New York

    Google Scholar 

  150. Pareto V (1935) The mind and society [Trattato di Sociologia Generale]. Harcourt, Brace, New York

    Google Scholar 

  151. Parfit D (2011) On what matters. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  152. Parker G (2013) Global crisis. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT

    Google Scholar 

  153. Penn E (2009) A model of far-sighted voting. Am J Polit Sci 53:36–54

    Google Scholar 

  154. Plott CR (1967) A notion of equilibrium and its possibility under majority rule. Am Econ Rev 57:787–806

    Google Scholar 

  155. Pugh CC (2002) Real mathematical analysis. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  156. Putnam RD, Campbell DE (2010) American grace: how religion divides and Unites Us. Simon and Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  157. Rader T (1972) Theory of general economic equilibrium. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  158. Rae D (1960) Decision Rules and Individual Values in Constitutional Choice. American Political Science Review 63:40–56

    Google Scholar 

  159. Richards (1990) Is strategic decisionmaking chaotic? Behavioral Science 35:219–232

    Google Scholar 

  160. Robson AJ, Kaplan HS (2003) The evolution of human life expectancy and intelligence in hunter-gatherer economies. American Economic Review 93:150–169

    Google Scholar 

  161. Rogow (1986) Thomas Hobbes Norton. New York

    Google Scholar 

  162. Saari D (1985) Price dynamics, social choice, voting methods, probability and chaos. In: Aliprantis D, Burkenshaw O, Rothman NJ (eds) Lecture Notes in Economics and Mathematical Systems, vol 244. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  163. Saari D (1985) A chaotic exploration of aggregation paradoxes. SIAM Rev 37:37–52

    Google Scholar 

  164. Saari, D (1995) Mathematical complexity of simple economics. Notes Am Math Soc 42:222–230

    Google Scholar 

  165. Saari D (1997) The generic existence of a core for q-rules. Econ Theory 9:219–260

    Google Scholar 

  166. Saari D (2001) Decisions and elections: explaining the unexpected. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  167. Saari D (2001) Chaotic elections. American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI

    Google Scholar 

  168. Saari D (2008) Disposing dictators, demystifying voting paradoxes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  169. Schofield N (1972) Is majority rule special? In: Niemi RG, Weisberg HF (eds) Probability models of collective decision-making. Charles E. Merrill Publishing Co, Columbus, OH

    Google Scholar 

  170. Schofield N (1972) Ethical decision rules for uncertain voters. Br J Polit Sci 2:193–207

    Google Scholar 

  171. Schofield N (1975) A game theoretic analysis of Olson’s game of collective action. J Confl Resolut 19:441–461

    Google Scholar 

  172. Schofield N (1977) The logic of catastrophe. Hum Ecol 5:261–271

    Google Scholar 

  173. Schofield N (1978) Instability of simple dynamic games. Rev Econ Stud 45:575–594

    Google Scholar 

  174. Schofield N (1979) Rationality or chaos in social choice. Greek Econ Rev 1:61–76

    Google Scholar 

  175. Schofield N (1980) Generic properties of simple Bergson-Samuelson welfare functions. J Math Econ 7:175–192

    Google Scholar 

  176. Schofield N (1980) Catastrophe theory and dynamic games. Qual Quant 14:529–545

    Google Scholar 

  177. Schofield N (1983) Equilibria in simple dynamic games. In: Pattanaik P, Salles M (eds) Social choice and welfare, pp 269–284. North Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  178. Schofield N (1983) Generic instability of majority rule. Rev Econ Stud 50:695–705

    Google Scholar 

  179. Schofield N (1984) Existence of equilibrium on a manifold. Math Oper Res 9:545–557

    Google Scholar 

  180. Schofield N (1984) Social equilibrium and cycles on compact sets. J Econ Theory 33:59–71

    Google Scholar 

  181. Schofield N (1984) Classification theorem for smooth social choice on a manifold. Soc Choice Welf 1:187–210

    Google Scholar 

  182. Schofield N (1985) Anarchy, altruism and cooperation. Soc Choice Welf 2:207–219

    Google Scholar 

  183. Schofield N, Tovey C (1992) Probability and convergence for supra-majority rule with Euclidean preferences. Math Comput Model 16:41–58

    Google Scholar 

  184. Schofield N (1999) The heart and the uncovered set. J Econ Suppl 8:79–113

    Google Scholar 

  185. Schofield N (1999) A smooth social choice method of preference aggregation. In: Wooders M (ed) Topics in mathematical economics and game theory: essays in honor of R. Aumann. Fields Institute, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI

    Google Scholar 

  186. Schofield N (1999) The C 1−topology on the space of smooth preferences. Soc Choice Welf 16:445–470

    Google Scholar 

  187. Schofield N (2002) Evolution of the constitution. Br J Polit Sci 32:1–20

    Google Scholar 

  188. Schofield N (2003) Mathematical methods in economics and social choice. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  189. Schofield N (2006) Architects of political change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  190. Schofield N (2007) The mean voter theorem: necessary and sufficient conditions for convergent equilibrium. Rev Econ Stud 74:965–980

    Google Scholar 

  191. Schofield N (2010) Social orders. Soc Choice Welf 34:503–536

    Google Scholar 

  192. Schofield N (2011) Is the political economy stable or chaotic? Czech Econ Rev 5:76–93

    Google Scholar 

  193. Schofield N, Gallego M (2011) Leadership or chaos. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  194. Schweitzer F et al (2009) Economic networks: the new challenges. Science 325:422–425

    Google Scholar 

  195. Shafer W, Sonnenschein H (1975) Equilibrium in abstract economies without ordered preferences. J Math Econ 2:245–248

    Google Scholar 

  196. Shiller R (2003) The new financial order. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  197. Shiller R (2005) Irrational exuberance. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  198. Smale S (1966) Structurally stable systems are not dense. Am J Math 88:491–496

    Google Scholar 

  199. Smale S (1974) Global analysis and economics IIA: extension of a theorem of Debreu. J Math Econ 1:1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  200. Smale S (1974) Global analysis and economics IV: finiteness and stability of equilibria with general consumption sets and production. J Math Econ 1:119–127

    Google Scholar 

  201. Smith A (1984 [1759]) The theory of moral sentiments. Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, IN

    Google Scholar 

  202. Sperber J (2011). Karl Marx: a nineteenth century life. Liveright, New York

    Google Scholar 

  203. Smolin L (2007) The trouble with physics. Houghton Mifflin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  204. Strnad J (1985) The structure of continuous-valued neutral monotonic social functions. Soc Choice Welf 2:181–195

    Google Scholar 

  205. Strogatz S (2004) Sync. Hyperion, New York

    Google Scholar 

  206. Stern N (2007) The economics of climate change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  207. Stern N (2009) The global deal. Public Affairs, New York

    Google Scholar 

  208. Stringer C (2012) Lone Survivors. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  209. Sunstein CR (2006) Infotopia. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  210. Sunstein CR (2009) A constitution of many minds. Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ

    Google Scholar 

  211. Sunstein CR (2011) Going to extremes. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  212. Surowiecki J (2005) The wisdom of crowds. Anchor, New York

    Google Scholar 

  213. Taleb NN (2007) The black swan. Random, New York

    Google Scholar 

  214. Taleb NN, Blyth M (2011) The black swan of Cairo. Foreign Affairs 90(3):33–39

    Google Scholar 

  215. Taylor M (1976) Anarchy and cooperation. Wiley, London

    Google Scholar 

  216. Taylor M (1982) Community, anarchy and liberty. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  217. Taylor C (2007) A secular age. Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  218. Trivers R (1971) The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Q Rev Biol 46:35–56

    Google Scholar 

  219. Trivers R (1985) Social evolution. Cummings, Menlo Park, CA

    Google Scholar 

  220. Turing A (1937) On computable numbers with an application to the entscheidungs problem. Proc Lond Math Soc 42:230–265. Reprinted in Jack Copeland (ed) The essential turing. The Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  221. Walker M (1977) On the existence of maximal elements. J Econ Theory 16:470–474

    Google Scholar 

  222. Watts D (2002) A simple model of global cascades on random networks. Proc Natl Acad Sci 99:5766–5771

    Google Scholar 

  223. Watts D (2003) Six degrees. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  224. Weber M (1904) The Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism. Reprinted in 1997 by Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  225. Weitzman M (2009) Additive damages, fat-tailed climate dynamics, and uncertain discounting. Economics 3:1–22

    Google Scholar 

  226. White TD et al (2009) Ardipithicus ramidus and the paleobiology of early hominids Science 326:64–86

    Google Scholar 

  227. Wright R (2009) The moral animal Vintage. New York

    Google Scholar 

  228. Zeeman EC (1977) Catastrophe theory: selected papers, 1972–1977. Addison Wesley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  229. Zeeman EC (1992) Evolution and Catstrophe Theory. In: Bourriau (ed) Understanding catastrophe. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  230. Zhang DD et al (2007) Global climate change, war, and population decline in recent human history. Proc Natl Acad Sci 104(49):19214–19219

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Norman Schofield .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schofield, N. (2015). Climate Change and Social Choice Theory. In: Binder, C., Codognato, G., Teschl, M., Xu, Y. (eds) Individual and Collective Choice and Social Welfare. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-46439-7_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics