Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Schriftenreihe der Wittgenstein-Gesellschaft ((SWG,volume 19/1))

Abstract

Queen Anne is dead. That sentence expresses a truth; it does so because its subject term refers to someone — Queen Anne — who satisfies its predicate, and therefore — if death is the end of existence — no longer exists. But then what is left for ‘Queen Anne’ to refer to?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 44.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. I am indebted in these paragraphs and elsewhere to Nathan Salmon, “Existence”, in Philo-so phical Perspectives 1: Metaphysics, ed. James Tomberlin (Atascadero, 1987 ).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ruth Barcan Marcus, “The identity of individuals in a strict functional calculus of second order”, Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 12 (1947); Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Oxford, 1980), pp. 3–5.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Allan Gibbard, “Contingent identity”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 4 (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Compare Russell’s reply to the question after Lecture V of “The philosophy of logical atomism”, at p. 99 of the reprint in Russell’s Logical Atomism,ed. David Pears (London, 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Some arguments used in defence of existence as a predicate, such as those in John Mackie, “The riddle of existence”, Aristotelian Society,Sup. Vol. 50 (1976), are also applicable to the case of objecthood.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Kripke (1980), p. 108n. For more on this style of argument see Timothy Williamson, “Equivocation and Existence”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,Vol. 88 (1987/8), at pp. 111–14.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Strictly speaking the argument assumes that =, and =2 obey reflexivity and the identity of indiscernibles in the sense of necessarily satisfying them, otherwise =1 and =2 would not have been shown to be necessarily equivalent. That is permissible, for strictly speaking identity should be characterized as necessarily the smallest reflexive relation, that is, the relation which is necessarily reflexive and at least as small as any reflexive relation. Without the modal gloss, no relation is uniquely singled out.

    Google Scholar 

  8. A reflexive relation is here understood as one that any object (existent or not) has to itself.

    Google Scholar 

  9. David Wiggins, Sameness and Substance (Oxford, 1980), at pp. 109–11 and 214–15.

    Google Scholar 

  10. G.E. Hughes and M.J. Cresswell, An Introduction to Modal Logic (London, 1968), at p. 190.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Nathan Salmon, “The logic of what might have been”, Philosophical Review, Vol. 98 (1989), at p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Strictly speaking the argument assumes that E1 and E2 obey the objecthood principle in the sense of necessarily satisfying it, otherwise they would not have been shown to be necessarily equivalent. That is permissible, for strictly speaking objecthood should be characterized as necessarily the largest property, that is, the property which is necessarily at least as large as any property. Without the modal gloss, no property is uniquely singled out. A parallel argument about existence is discussed at pp. 115–17 of Williamson (1987/8).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Compare Robert Stalnaker, “Complex predicates”, Monist, Vol. 60 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Saul Kripke, “Semantical considerations on modal logic”, Acta Philosophica Fennica,Vol. 16 (1963), reprinted in Reference and Modality,ed. Leonard Linsky (Oxford, 1971), where the relevant passage is at pp. 67–8.

    Google Scholar 

  15. A similar case is Joseph Almog, “Logic and the world”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 18 (1989). The non-contingency of objecthood may provide a theoretical justification for the claim that structural traits of the world are essential to it, without which Almog suggests we are not entitled to assume that logical truths are necessary. Of course, some candidates for contingent logical truths remain, such as those of the form “A if and only if actually A”, but these are perhaps less deeply contingent.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Williamson (1987/8), at pp. 117–22.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See Wiggins (1980) at pp. 27–36 on the need for such distinctions.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The conclusion resembles one of Ramsey’s. For recent discussion of his arguments see Allen Hazen, “A fallacy in Ramsey”, Mind,Vol. 95 (1986), and Almog (1989). On the present view, the number of existents remains a contingent matter, in a sense.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Rudolf Haller Johannes Brandl

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1990 Springer-Verlag Wien

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Williamson, T. (1990). Necessary Identity and Necessary Existence. In: Haller, R., Brandl, J. (eds) Wittgenstein — Eine Neubewertung / Wittgenstein — Towards a Re-Evaluation. Schriftenreihe der Wittgenstein-Gesellschaft, vol 19/1. J.F. Bergmann-Verlag, Munich. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-30086-2_15

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-30086-2_15

  • Publisher Name: J.F. Bergmann-Verlag, Munich

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-209-01122-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-30086-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics