Skip to main content

Functionalism and the “Systems Approach”

  • Chapter
Economics as Moral Science

Part of the book series: Studies in Economic Ethics and Philosophy ((SEEP))

  • 222 Accesses

Abstract

One aspect of the critical problem concerning competing mechanistic and teleological interpretations of the structure of social scientific theories in general, and CCT in particular, which raises especially important questions about normative presuppositions, is that of the “functional” structure of certain theories. Significantly, the implications of the use of functional terms in everyday discourse has also played an important role in arguments defending and attacking the affirmation of a “fact-value” or “is-ought” separation in ethical theory itself. This chapter will begin, therefore, with an attempt to show that the analysis of functionalist language within ethical theory helps to clarify the issue of the “value-impregnation” of functionalist theories of human behaviour. Following upon this task will be an elucidation of the functionalist structure of explanations of consumer behaviour provided by CCT, and an appraisal of the explanatory and normative adequacy of placing such a structure within a general systems theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See, for instance, P. Geach, “Good and Evil”, in Analysis, Vol. 17 (1956), pp. 33–42.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See e.g., R. M. Hare, “Geach: Good and Evil”, Analysis, Vol. 18 (1957), pp. 10212.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See C. G. Hempel, “The Logic of Functional Analysis”, in his Aspects of Scientific Explanation, pp. 297–330 for a useful general survey of the concepts and structure of functionalist theories.

    Google Scholar 

  4. For the classic source of systems theory see L. von Bertalanffy, General Systems Theory (New York: G. Braziller, 1968). A recent overview is provided in George J. Klir, Facets of Systems Science (New York: Plenum Press, 1994). For a philosopher’s perspective, see C. W. Churchman, The Systems Approach and its Enemies (New York: Basic Books, 1978). For an example of a mechanistic approach to systems see James G. Miller, “Introduction” in Chicago Behavioural Sciences Publications No.1: Profits and Problems of Homeostatic Models in the Behavioural Sciences (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1954). For an affirmation that mechanistic structures are inappropriate to explain the behaviour of “higher level” systems such as individual agents and social groups, see E. Laszlo, System,Structure and Experience (New York: Gordon and Beach Science Publishers, 1969), Chap. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For the claim that system approaches to economic theory are based primarily on an analogy with mechanistic systems, see P. Mirowski, More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as Nature’s Economics, and see the articles by A. J. Cohen, D. W. Hands, B. Barnes, M. N. Wise, “Review Symposium” on Mirowski’s book in Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Vol. 22, No. 1, March 1992, pp. 78–141. See also, G. Pikier, “Utility, Theories in Field Physics and Mathematical Economics, 1I and II”, K. Boulding, “General Systems Theory ¡ª The Skeleton of a Science” in his Beyond Economics (Ann Arbour: University of Michigan Press, 1968), especially pp. 95–97, and F. H. Knight, On the History and Method of Economics, Chap. VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  6. L. von Bertalanffy, General Systems Theory, p. 55. See note 4 to Chapter 4 above.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Again, see F. Machlup, “Equilibrium and Disequilibrium” for a discussion of the concept of equilibrium in economic theory.

    Google Scholar 

  8. 1bid., p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind, Chap. IV, sec. 6 for an analysis of this difficulty for hedonistic explanations generally.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See for example, R. Leftwich, The Price System and Resource Allocation, 3rd edn., (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1966), p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  11. As suggested, for instance, by J. Rothenberg, “Values and Value Theory in Economics”, pp. 227f and p. 237; or by the philosopher D. Braybrooke, “Economics and Rational Choice”, p. 455.

    Google Scholar 

  12. An influential case in point is I. D. M. Little, A Critique of Welfare Economics, Chaps. 1 and 2.

    Google Scholar 

  13. W. J. Baumol, Economic Theory and Operations Analysis, pp. 204–05.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 205.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Such as Little, A Critique of Welfare Economics, Chap. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See Mark Blaug, Economic Theory in Retrospect, p. 356.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Again, Little, A Critique of Welfare Economics, Chap. 2, will be taken as a representative case of such economic behaviourism.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See p. 44 above.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Little, A Critique of Welfare Economics, p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See K. Boulding, “Some Contributions of Economics to the General Theory of Value”, Philosophy of Science,Vol. 23, no. 1, 1956, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Little, A Critique of Welfare Economics, p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., p. 42ff.

    Google Scholar 

  24. In economic language, such a situation is known as the problem of “interdependent utility functions”. See L. D. Schally “Interdependent Utility Functions and Pareto Optimality”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 86, 1972, pp. 19–24.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Little, A Critique of Welfare Economics, p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See, on this issue, the classic discussion of emulative consumption in J. S. Duesenberry, Income, Saving and the Theory of Consumer Behaviour (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1949), Chap. 3, sec. 5, pp. 28–32. And see E. J. Mishan, “The Growth of Affluence and the Decline of Welfare”, p. 271.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See pp. 46f. above.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hodgson, B. (2001). Functionalism and the “Systems Approach”. In: Economics as Moral Science. Studies in Economic Ethics and Philosophy. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04476-6_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04476-6_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-07427-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-04476-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics