Advertisement

The Relevance of Philosophy to Physics

Chapter
Part of the Studies in the Foundations, Methodology and Philosophy of Science book series (FOUNDATION, volume 4)

Abstract

My thesis, that philosophy is relevant to physics, is unfashionable, to say the least. This minority view gives me some strange bedfellows: for example, some people with particular regions views who are anxious to make science agree with theology (although primarily their interest is in geology and biology, rather than in physics) [32]. I prefer the company of those philosophers who have been influenced by Sir KARL POPPER’S almost lone defence of the meaningfulness of non-scientific statements — lone, in the sense that POPPER fought in the interests of science [2,10,13, 34, 35]. By contrast, the majority view is either a deliberate rejection of philosophy, especially metaphysics, as false (or meaningless or irrelevant), or a simple ignoring of the problems of which philosophy has traditionally been the study. Nevertheless, neither rejecting philosophy nor ignoring it imphes that solutions to philosophical problems are not adopted. On the contrary, it is customary for the majority to adopt a stance which is a mixture of various solutions to a number of still puzzling philosophical problems but which interferes as little as possible with scientific work [39]. Furthermore, it is customary to fend off all attempts at serious discussion of those problems in case such discussion should have mischievous effects on the progress of science.

Keywords

Physical Theory Inductive Logic Moral Consideration Philosophical Problem Critical Debate 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Agassi, J.: The confusion between physics and metaphysics in the standard histories of science. Ithaca 26, 231–244 (1962).Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    — The nature of scientific problems and their roots in metaphysics (M. Bunge, ed.). The critical approach to science and philosophy. London 1964.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    — The confusion between science and technology in standard philosophies of science. Technology and Culture 7, 348–366 (1966).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    — Positive evidence in science and technology. Philos. Sci. 37, 261–270 (1970).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Aristotle: Prior analytics.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Ayer, Sir A.J.: Language, truth and logic. London 1936.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    — (ed.): Logical positivism., New York 1959.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Bacon, Sir FRANCIS: Novum Organon.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Bridgmann, P.W.: The nature of physical theory., Princeton 1936 Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Bunge, M.: Metascientific queries. Springfield, 111. 1959.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    — Physical axiomatics. Rev. Modern Phys. 39, 463–474 (1967).ADSzbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    — (ed.): Quantum theory and reality., New York 1968.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    — Scientific research., New York 1968.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    — What are physical theories about? Amer. Philos. Quart. Monograph No. 3, 61–99 (1969).Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    — Theory meets experience. Mind, science and history. Albany, New York 1970.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Carnap, R.: Logical foundations of probability., Chicago 1950zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  17. 17.
    — Philosophical foundations of physics., New York 1966.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Descartes, R.: Discours de la Méthode.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    — Méditations.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Deutscher, M.: Popper’s problem of an empirical basis. Austral. J. Philos. 46, 277–288 (1968).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Duhem, P.: La Théorie Physique; Son Objet, Sa Structure. Paris 1907.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Feigl, H.,BRODBECK, M. (eds): Readings in the philosophy of science. New York 1953.Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Good, I.J.: Kinds of probability. Science 129, 443–447 (1959).MathSciNetADSzbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Hempel, C.: Aspects of scientific explanation. New York 1965.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Hume,D.: Inquiry concerning human understanding.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Kant,I.: Kritik der reinen VernunftGoogle Scholar
  27. 27.
    Lakatos, I.: Changes in the problem of inductive logic. In: I. Lakatos (ed.). The problem of inductive logic. Amsterdam 1968.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Lewis,S.: Arrowsmith.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Maimonides, M.: The guide for the perplexed.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Maxwell, G.: The ontological status of theoretical entities. In: H. Feigl and G.Maxwell(eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science III. Minneapolis 1962.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Neurath, O.,CARNAP, R., MORRIS, C., (eds.): International encyclopedia of unified science., Chicago 1939.Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Peter, W. G., Ill: Fundamentalist scientists oppose Darwinian evolution. Bioscience, 20, 1067–1069 (1970).Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Popper, Sir K.R.: The aim of science. Ratio 1 (1957).Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    — The logic of scientific discovery. London 1959.zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  35. 35.
    —. Conjecture and refutations. London 1963.Google Scholar
  36. 36.
    — The propensity interpretation of probability. British J. Philos. Sci. 10 25–42 (1959).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. 37.
    Salmon, W.C.: The foundations of scientific inference., Pittsburgh 1966.Google Scholar
  38. 38.
    — Justification of inductive rules of inference. In: I. Lakatos (ed.). The problem of inductive logic., Amsterdam 1968.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Settle, T.W.: Scientists: Priests of pseudo-certainty of prophets of inquiry? Science Forum, 2 No. 3, 22–24 (1969).Google Scholar
  40. 40.
    — Deutscher’s problem is not Popper‘s problem. Austral. J. Philos. 47, 216–219 (1969).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. 41.
    — The point of positive evidence: Reply to Professor Feyerabend. British J. Philos. Sci. 20, 352–355 (1969).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. 42.
    — Confirmation as a probability: Dead but it won’t he down. British J. Philos. Sci. 21,200–201 (1970).Google Scholar
  43. 43.
    — Is corroboration a non-demonstrative form of inference? Ratio(forthcoming).Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    — Review of R. Dubos, Reason awake: Science for man and N. Calder, Technopolis: the social control of the uses of science. In: Science Forum 18,18–21 (1970).Google Scholar
  45. 45.
    — Induction and probability unfused. In: P.A. Schilpp (ed.).The philosophy of Karl R. Popper(forthcoming).Google Scholar
  46. 46.
    WhiteA.D.:A history of the warfare of science with theology. New York 1960 Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag Berlin · Heidelberg 1971

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of GuelphGuelphCanada

Personalised recommendations