Skip to main content

Grammar and Interpretation

  • Chapter
Computation of Language

Part of the book series: Symbolic Computation ((1064))

  • 101 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter presents basic criteria of adequacy for grammars. Section 2.1 explains the empirical limitations of constituent-structure analysis. Section 2.2 presents the basic theory of natural-language communication. Section 2.3 illustrates the process of understanding a sentence with a simple formal example. Section 2.4 presents the Criteria of Psychological Well-Foundedness. Section 2.5 shows that grammars within current paradigms of linguistic analysis are not psychologically well-founded.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Bloomfield (1933), Wells (1947), Harris (1951), Bloch (1953). For a more recent discussion of syntactic hierarchies from the viewpoint of tagmemic grammar see Longacre (1983), pp. 273 f.

    Google Scholar 

  2. “In short, the approach to the analysis of grammaticalness suggested here in terms of a finite state Markov process that produces sentences from left to right, appears to lead to a dead end.” Chomsky (1957), p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Hausser (1979b,c).

    Google Scholar 

  4. McDonald et al. (1987) use the term “relevant portion of the situation” or RPS (op. cit., p. 161). We avoid the term “situation” because it is biased toward a description of the external world, rather than certain internal states of the speaker or the hearer. For a related discussion see Section 12.5.

    Google Scholar 

  5. STAR-point stands for the Space-Time-Agent-Recipient point of origin of a sign.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See pp. 103 f. of Anderson and Bower (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  7. E.g., Quine (1960).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Section 11.2 for further discussion.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The exact definitions of the intensional logic used in 2.3.2 are explicitly given in Section 15.5.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Much of the discussion of semantics and pragmatics in Chapters 11–15 will be formulated in model-theoretic terms.

    Google Scholar 

  11. As, for example, in Sowa (1984), p. 302.

    Google Scholar 

  12. For reasons explained in Section 3.4, semantic frame-names like FIDO-l_l_l consist of two parts, namely the base, e.g., FIDO, and the index, e.g., -1_1_1.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Since the frame-theoretic icon is build simultaneously with the left-associative derivation (cf. Section 3.3), pragmatic interpretation may commence during the syntactico/semantic analysis.

    Google Scholar 

  14. I.e., a sequence of word forms, such as Fido found a bone.

    Google Scholar 

  15. A methodological desideratum inherited from generative grammar in general. See Section 6.1.

    Google Scholar 

  16. That the hearer is often able to guess the continuation, enabling him to complete the sentence before the speaker, provides additional support to a linear (or left-associative) approach to syntax.

    Google Scholar 

  17. A limiting case of a continuation is the speaker’s decision to break off and start over (‘false starts’). “Speech is irreversible. That is its fatality. What has been said cannot be unsaid, except by adding to it: to correct here, is, oddly enough, to continue.” (R. Barthes, 1986, p. 76).

    Google Scholar 

  18. The bidirectional surface-meaning mapping and the time-linear derivation order constitute necessary, but not sufficient, I/O-conditions of language use. That is, while no natural-language use will violate these conditions, there may well be further constraints.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Only clauses 2 and 3 of the Criteria of Procedural Adequacy are relevant for I/O-equivalence with the speaker-hearer. Clause 1 is not specifically excluded, however, because the explicit formal statement of the grammatical rules is a methodological precondition for evaluating clauses 2 and 3 in a meaningful way.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The formalism of C-grammar is based on Lesnieswki (1929) and Ajdukiewicz (1935). This formalism was first applied to the description of natural language by Bar-Hillel (1953).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Montague (1974), Chapter 8, henceforth “PTQ.”

    Google Scholar 

  22. Hausser (1984a).

    Google Scholar 

  23. The formalism of PS-grammar is based on the rewriting systems of Post (1936). This formalism was first applied to the description of natural language by Chomsky (1957).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Chomsky (1965).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Chomsky (1981).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Bresnan (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Gazdar et al. (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  28. R and lambda-reduction are many-one functions, and their inverses one-many relations. See Hausser (1984a), chapters 2 and 4, for further discussion.

    Google Scholar 

  29. The same holds for the derivational structure of the current competitors of GB.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hausser, R. (1989). Grammar and Interpretation. In: Computation of Language. Symbolic Computation. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-74564-5_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-74564-5_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-74566-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-74564-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics