Skip to main content

On Literacy and the Myth of Literal Meaning

  • Chapter
Book cover The Written World

Part of the book series: Springer Series in Language and Communication ((SSLAN,volume 23))

Abstract

Issues concerning literalness of meaning range all the way from folk linguistics to axiomatic features of formalized semantic theory. Acceptance of “literal” as a primitive, undefined term in delineation of an autonomous field of “pure” semantics may hence be in part due to the intuitive appeal of pervading pretheoretical notions such as, for instance (Goffman, 1976, p. 303), “... the common sense notion... that the word in isolation will have a general basic, or most down-to-earth meaning...”. Such presuppositions seem to form part of the myth of literal meaning in our highly literate societies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Allwood, J. (1981). On the distinction between semantics and pragmatics. In W. Klein W. Levelt (Eds.), Crossing the boundaries in linguistics. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G. P.,Hacker, P. M. S. (1980). Wittgenstein. Meaning and understanding. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M. (1973). Problems of Dostoevsky’s poetics. Ann Arbor: Ardis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. (1985). The situation in logic: Part 2. Conditionals and conditional information. Mimeo; Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1934). Sprachtheorie. Jena: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1974). Of grammatology. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1979). What computers can’t do. The limits of artificial intelligence. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1977). A theory of semantics. London: McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, C. F., Winograd, T. (1983). Understanding computers and cognition: A new foundation for design. Mimeo, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1969). Funktion, Begriff, Bedeutung. Fünf logische Studien. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • F0llesdal, D. (1983). Situation semantics and the “slingshot” argument. Erkenntnis

    Google Scholar 

  • Geva, E., Olson, D. (1983). Children’s story telling. First Language, 4, 85–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1976). Replies and responses. Language in Society, 5, 257–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking. Hassocks: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1981). Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, I&II. Frankfurt: Suhr-kamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1974). Thought. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausser, R. R. (1983). On vagueness. Journal of Semantics, 2, 273–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildyard, A., Olson, D. R. (1982). On the structure and meaning of prose text. In W. Otto S. White (Eds.), Reading Expository Material (pp. 155–184 ). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., Kulas, J. (1982). Russell vindicated: Towards a general theory of definite descriptions. Journal of Semantics, 1, 387–397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J. J. (1981). Literal meaning and logical theory. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 203–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1977). Identity and necessity. In S. P. Schwartz (Ed.), Naming, necessity, and natural kinds (pp. 66–101 ). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, J. (1978). Desire in language. A semiotic approach to literature and art. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levelt, W.J.M. (1983). The speaker’s organization of discourse. In S. Hattori K. Inoue (Eds.), Proceedings of the XIIIth International Congress of Linguists (pp. 278–279 ). Tokyo: Proceedings Publishing Committee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levelt, W. J. M. (1984). Spontaneous self-repairs in speech: Processes and represen-tations. Mimeo, Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levelt, W.J.M., Cutler, A. (1983). Prosodic marking in speech repair. Journal of Semantics, 2, 205–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linell, P. (1982). The written language bias in linguistics. Linköping University, Studies in Communication 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malinowski, B. (1984). “Magic, science and religion” and other essays. Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marslen-Wilson, W., Komisarjevsky-Tyler, L. (1980). The temporal structure of spoken language understanding. Cognition, 8, 1–17.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H.P., Varela, F.J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition. The realization of the living. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mukarovsky, J. (1976). On poetic language. Lisse: Peter de Ridder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naess, A. (1969). Hvilken verden er den virkelige? [Which world is the real one?] Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, D. (1982). Perspective taking versus content in understanding lies. The Quarterly Newsletter of the Laboratory of Comparative Human Cognition, 4, 26–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, D. R. (1977). From utterance to text: The bias of language in speech and writing. Harvard Educational Review, 47, 257–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, D. R., Torrance, N. G. (1985). Literacy and cognitive development: A con-ceptual transformation in the early school years. Mimeo. To appear in S. Meadows (Ed.), Issues in childhood cognitive development. London: Methuen Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1971). Objective knowledge. An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clar-endon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Meaning and the moral sciences. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1980). Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundations of cognitive science. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 111–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rommetveit, R. (1974). On message structure. A framework for the study of language and communication, London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rommetveit, R. (1979). On “meanings” of acts and what is meant by what is said in a pluralistic social world. In M. Brenner (Ed.), The Structure of Action (pp. 108–149 ). Oxford: Blackwell Mott.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rommetveit, R. (1983 a). Prospective social psychological contributions to a truly interdisciplinary understanding of ordinary language. Journal of Language and Social Psychology, 2, 89–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rommetveit, R. (1983 b). In search of a truly interdisciplinary semantics. A sermon on hopes of salvation from hereditary sins. Journal of Semantics,2, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rommetveit, R. (1984). The role of language in the creation and transmission of social representations. In R. M. Farr S. Moscovici (Eds.), Social representations (pp. 331–359 ). Paris and Cambridge: Maison des Sciences de l’Homme and Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rommetveit R. (1985). Language acquisition as increasing linguistic structuring of experience and symbolic behavior control. In J. V. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture, communication and cognition: Vygotskian perspectives (pp. 183–204 ). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, A. (1945). On multiple realities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5, 533–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1974). On speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1978). Literal meaning. Erkenntnis, 13, 207–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1979). Metaphor. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought (pp. 92–123 ). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S (1970). Reasons and causes. In R. Borger F. Cioffi (Eds.), Explanation in the behavioral sciences (pp. 1–26 ). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vologinov, V. N. (1973). Marxism and the philosophy of language. New York: Seminar Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1962). Thought and language, New York: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winograd, T. (1985). Moving the semantic fulcrum. Linguistics and Philosophy, 8, 91–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1974). Causality and determinism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1988 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rommetveit, R. (1988). On Literacy and the Myth of Literal Meaning. In: Säljö, R. (eds) The Written World. Springer Series in Language and Communication, vol 23. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-72877-8_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-72877-8_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-72879-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-72877-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics