Skip to main content

Philosophy and Method in Biological Classification

  • Chapter
Numerical Taxonomy

Part of the book series: NATO ASI Series ((ASIG,volume 1))

Abstract

Classifications are designed for various purposes. In most of science they are pragmatic, with general purpose classifications (in philosophy of science termed natural classifications, and phenetic in outlook) used as a basis. These are supplemented by others for special purposes. In biology there is debate on the type of classification that is proper as a basis; the main contendants for this are phenetic and phylogenetic classifications.

The difference between falsifiability and verifiability is discussed. Phenetic classifications (using agreed data and algorithms) are verifiable. Phylogenetic classifications are not verifiable because actual phylogenies are unknown. A phylogenetic reconstruction depends critically on assumptions on how evolution operates, and on whether evolution did operate thus in that particular instance. These assumptions, and whether they operated, cannot be tested directly. It is not desirable to base science on the unverifiable.

Distinction is drawn between classifications derived from a small sample of data and those from a large or complete data set. Analogies are drawn between these and the statistical concepts of samples and populations. Difficulties in these concepts are discussed.

The logic of phylogenetic reconstruction is briefly discussed. Evolutionary homology cannot be a basis for classification because evolutionary homologies are unknown and must be deduced from the classification itself. What can be known is isology or high one-to-one correspondence in complex structures or systems. Phylogenetic work faces the same kind of methodological problems with character weighting, similarity coefficients and the like, as phenetics. Monophyletic groups that depart too much from phenetic groups are not useful for general taxonomy.

It is concluded that phenetic classifications are preferable as general purpose classifications, and their aim is to maximize the number of predictive statements about members of their constituent classes. This can be measured in terms of information content in a number of ways. Those most appropriate for biological systematics are discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Cain, A.J. 1962. The evolution of taxonomic principles. Symp. Soc. Gen. Microbiol. 12: 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correll, R.L. 1977. The application of maximal predictive classification to the Epacridaceae. Taxon 26: 65–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N. and J. Cracraft. 1980. Phylogenetic Patterns and the Evolutionary Process. Method and Theory in Comparative Biology. Columbia University Press, New York. 349 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein, J. 1981. A likelihood approach to character weighting and what it tells us about parsimony and compatability. Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 16: 183–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funk, V.A. and D.R. Brooks. 1981. National Science Foundation Workshop on the Theory and Application of Cladistic Methodology. Organized by T. Duncan and T. Stuessy. University of California, Berkley, 22–28 March 1981. Syst. Zool. 30: 491–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilmour, J.S.L. 1937. A taxonomic problem. Nature 139:1040–1042. Gilmour, J.S.L. 1940. Taxonomy and philosophy. Pages 461–474 in

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig, W. 1950. Grundzuge einer Theorie der phylogenetischen Systematik. Deutscher Zentralverlag, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig, W. 1966. Phylogenetic Systematics. University of Illinois Press, Urbana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig, W. 1950. Grundzuge einer Theorie der phylogenetischen Systematik. Deutscher Zentralverlag, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphries, C.J. and P.M. Richardson. 1980. Hennig’s method and phytochemistry. Pages 353–378 in F.A. Bisby, J.G. Vaughan, and C.A. Wright, eds. Chemosystematics: Principles and Practice. Academic Press, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, N. 1969. The observational and theoretical components of homology: a study based on the morphology of the dermal skull-roofs of ripidistian fishes. Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 1: 327–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Quesne, W.J. 1982. Compatibility analysis and its applications. Zool. J. Linn. Soc. 74: 267–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, G. and N. Platnick. 1981. Systematics and Biogeography. Cladistics and Vicariance. Columbia University Press, New York. 567 pp. Panchen

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, C. 1982. Morphological characters and homology. Pages 2174 in K.A. Joysey and A.E. Friday, eds. Problems of Phylogenetic Reconstruction. Academic Press, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Quesne, W.J. 1982. Compatibility analysis and its applications. Zool. J. Linn. Soc. 74: 267–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, C. 1982. Morphological characters and homology. Pages 2174 in K.A. Joysey and A.E. Friday, eds. Problems of Phylogenetic Reconstruction. Academic Press, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohlf, F.J. and R.R. Sokal. 1981. Comparing numerical taxonomic studies. Syst. Zool. 30: 459–490.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. 1973. The Philosophy of Biology. Hutchinson and Co., London. 231 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seewaldt, E. and E. Stackebrandt. 1982. Partial sequence of 16S ribosomal RNA and the phylogeny of Prochloron. Nature 295: 618–620.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Sneath, P.H.A. 1974. Phylogeny of micro-organisms. Symp. Soc. Gen. Microbiol. 24: 1–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneath, P.H.A. 1980. The estimation of differences in protein evolution rates. Proc. Geol. Ass. 91: 71–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneath, P.H.A. 1982. Systematics and Biogeography. Cladistics and Vicariance. Gareth Nelson and Norman Platnick. 1981. Syst. Zool. 31: 219–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneath, P.H.A. and R.R. Sokal. 1973. Numerical Taxonomy. The Principles and Practice of Numerical Classification. W.H. Freeman and Co., San Francisco. 573 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal, R.R. and F.J. Rohlf. 1981. Taxonomic congruence in the Leptopodomorpha re-examined. Syst. Zool. 30: 309–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal, R.R. and P.H.A. Sneath. 1963. Principles of Numerical Taxonomy. W.H. Freeman and Co., San Francisco. 359 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woese, C. 1981. Archaebacteria. Sci. American 244: 94–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodger, J.H. 1945. On biological transformations. Pages 94–120 in W.E. Le Gros Clark and P.B. Medawar, eds. Essays on Growth and Form presented to D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson. Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • W.E. Le Gros Clark and P.B. Medawar, eds. Essays on Growth and Form presented to D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson. Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1983 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sneath, P.H.A. (1983). Philosophy and Method in Biological Classification. In: Felsenstein, J. (eds) Numerical Taxonomy. NATO ASI Series, vol 1. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-69024-2_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-69024-2_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-69026-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-69024-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics