Skip to main content

Freedom and Moral Judgment A Cognitive Model of Permissibility

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 8))

Abstract

Contemporary research in the fields of moral psychology and cognitive philosophy has provided considerable data supporting the claim that there are important similarities in the ways in which different people conceive of morality and produce moral judgments. However, one of the more pressing questions is how to account for the fact that, despite these similarities, moral judgments appear to be highly variable both on a cultural and individual level. This paper addresses this issue by developing a model which is inverted with respect to the one usually embraced by the cognitive literature on morality. Instead of analyzing the problem of moral judgment starting from all the actions that are considered impermissible, this work assumes that people first judge which actions are morally permissible. Permissibility is interpreted in terms of what each subject feels he/she must be free to do. The advantage of this inversion is that it allows us to make a connection between two lines of research that are usually considered unrelated: research on the processes underlying the production of moral judgments and research on the problem of determining how people understand ‘freedom’. Regarding this latter issue, the article focusses specifically on George Lakoff’s cognitive analysis of how humans develop their concepts of freedom. The starting point of Lakoff’s analysis is that different groups and different individuals do not have the same understanding of ‘freedom’, even though everybody shares the common empirical core concept. Lakoff puts forward a model which aims to explain both the common cognitive ground of the various concepts of freedom and how these concepts vary depending on other cognitive elements connected to them. In this work we try to show that Lakoff’s model can provide an explanation of moral judgment that accounts for both the cross-cultural and trans-individual similarities and the cultural, individual and situational differences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The existence of an innate moral faculty is hypothesized by e.g. [6], pp. 152–153, [18, 19, 27, 28, 30]; Haidt (see e.g. [13]) also speaks of a moral module, even though he maintains a different view according to which this module works with principles that are entirely derived by the culture the individuals belong to.

  2. 2.

    Haidt defines them as issues relating to harm/care and fairness/reciprocity.

  3. 3.

    For a critical examination of Haidt’s view showing—among other things—that the moral principles identified by Turiel and colleagues have a greater degree of universality compared to the ones identified by Haidt: see [9].

  4. 4.

    Haidt’s view tries to respond to the need for explaining why different cultures rely on different moral principles. However, de facto it binds moral evaluation entirely to cultural rules concluding that a virtuous person is a fully enculturated person ([14, p. 216]). Thus, Haidt bars the possibility of explaining those cases in which an individual moral judgment diverges from the rules expressed by the culture he/she belongs to and therefore fails to account for the individual and situational variability of moral judgment (on this issue see also [9]).

  5. 5.

    M. S. James, Prison Is ‘Living Hell' for Pedophiles, http://abcnews.go.com/US/story?id=90004#.T7o8BMXiYjk,abcNEWS Aug. 26, 2003.

  6. 6.

    It is not clear how this solution can preserve the analogy with Chomsky’s theory in relation to many factors, among others: what are the universal principles beyond this variability; why do people change their ‘moral parameters’ over time, when they should be set once and for all at an early developmental stage; how is it possible that ‘moral parameters’ are subject to exceptions, etc.

  7. 7.

    Immediately after the core concept is formed, we naturally, automatically and unconsciously extend it through metaphorical thought which accomplishes the function of linking “abstract ideas to visceral bodily experience.” [23]. The first extension is obtained by applying a so called “primary metaphor” which is basically universal and gives rise to a larger common core of the concept. (About primary metaphors (see e.g. [25, p. 46.]) The last and most important extension of the concept, as a consequence of which it takes its specific and individually different final abstract form, is carried out by inserting it into a so-called cognitive model: this step will be discussed below. For a more detailed analysis of Lakoff’s theory on the origin and development of the first stages of the concept of freedom see also [11].

  8. 8.

    The word cognitive indicates that they are mental theories: i.e. models internalized by the subject to understand the structure and the interconnections of specific complex phenomena, and to create links between concepts that allow their reciprocal determination. The word idealized suggests that the structures these models consist of “do not exist objectively in nature”, but “are created by human beings” [22, p. 69].

  9. 9.

    This definition of theories and of models resemble in a way that given by Thagard [38], even though for Thagard a model can only be computational, while Lakoff’s model is not meant to be computationally realizable.

  10. 10.

    Lakoff maintains that such a specification is possible in principle and gives important suggestions about how to develop it concretely. However, he doesn’t offer any systematic representation of ICMs, so, the structure of ICMs hasn’t been detailed yet.

References

  1. Arendt, H.: Eichman in Jerusalem: a Report on the Banality of the Evil. Addison-Wesley, London (1963–2006)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bandura, A.: Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement. In: Reich, W. (ed.) Origins of Terrorism: Psychologies, Ideologies, Theologies, States of Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Blair, R.J.R.: A Cognitive Developmental Approach to Morality: Investigating the Psychopath. Cognition 57, 1–29 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Boudreau, T.E., Polkinghorn, B.D.: Reversing the Destructive Discourses of Dehumanization: A Model for Reframing Narratives in Protracted Social Conflict through Identity Affirmation. Res. Soc. Mov. Conicts Chang. 29, 175–205 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Brown, D.: Human Universals. Temple University Press, Philadelphia (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Chomsky, N.: Language and Problems of Knowledge: The Managua Lectures. MIT Press, Cambridge (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Dellantonio, S.: Kognitive Module und moralische Kompetenz: Ist es möglich, der Moral eine biologische Grundlage zu geben? In: Fischer, M., Hengstschlger, M. (eds.) Genetic Screening. Ethik transdisziplinär Bd. 10. Peter Lang, Frankfurt a. M. (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Dellantonio, S., Job, R.: Morality According to a Cognitive Interpretation. A Semantic Model for Moral Behaviour. In: Magnani, L., Carnielli, W., Pizzi, C. (eds.) Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Springer, Berlin (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Dellantonio, S., Job, R.: Moral Intuitions vs. Moral Reasoning. A Philosophical Analysis of the Explanatory Models Intuitionism Relies on. In: Magnani, L., Li, P. (eds.) Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Springer, Berlin (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Dellantonio, S., Pastore, L.: Teorie morali e contenuto cognitivo. cognitivismo, postmoderno e relativismo cultural. In: Meattini, V., Pastore, L. (eds.) Individuo, identità, soggetto tra moderno e postmoderno. Mimesis, Milano (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Dellantonio, S., Pastore, L.: ‘Libertà’ senza significato? Concetti astratti, cognizione e determinismo linguistico. Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 2, 164–186 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Dwyer, S.: How Good is the Linguistic Analogy? In: Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., Stich, S. (eds.) The Innate Mind. Culture and Cognition, vol. 2. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Haidt, J.: The Emotional Dog and its Rational Tail: a Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment. Psychol. Rev. 108, 814–834 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F.: Social Intuitionists Answer Six Questions about Moral Psychology. In: Sinnott Armstrong, W. (ed.) Moral Psychology. Vol.2. The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity. MIT Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Haidt, J., Graham, J.: When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize. Soc. Justice Res. 20, 98–116 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Haidt, J., Graham, J.: Planet of the Durkheimians, where Community, Authority, and Sacredness are Foundations of Morality. In: Jost, J., A. C. Kay, H.T. (eds.) Social and Psychological Bases of Ideology and System Justification. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Haidt, J., Joseph, C.: The Moral Mind: How Five Sets of Innate Intuitions Guide the Development of Many Cultural-specic Virtues, and Perhaps Even Modules. In: Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., Stich, S. (eds.) The Innate Mind, vol. 3. Foundations and the Future. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Harman, G.: Explaining Value. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Hauser, M.D.: Moral Minds. How Nature Designed Our Moral Sense of Right and Wrong. Collins Publisher, New York (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Hooks, G., Mosher, C.: Outrages Against Personal Dignity: Rationalizing Abuse and Torture in the War on Terror. Soc. Forces 83, 1627–1646 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Kelly, D., Stich, S., Haley, K.J., Eng, S.J., Fessler, D.M.T.: Harm, Affect and the Moral/Conventional Distinction. Mind Lang. 22, 117–131 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Lakoff, G.: Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things. What Categories Reveal about the Mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Lakoff, G.: Whose Freedom? The Battle Over Americas Most Important Idea. Picador, USA (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Lakoff, G.: The Political Mind. Why You Cant Understand a 21st-Century Politics with an 18th-Century Brain. Viking, USA (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Lakoff, G., Johnson, M.: Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought. Basic Books, New York (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Merskin, D.: The Construction of Arabs as Enemies: Post-September 11 Discourse of George W. Bush. Mass Commun. Soc. 7, 157–175 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Mikheil, J.: Rawl’s Linguistic Analogy. Ph.D. Thesis Cornell University Press, New York (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Mikheil, J.M.: Law, Science and Morality: A Review of Richard Posner's 'The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory'. Stanf. Law Rev. 54, 1057–1127 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Nichols, S.: Mindreading and the Cognitive Architecture Underlying Altruistic Motivation. Mind Lang. 16, 425–455 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Nichols, S.: Sentimental Rules. On The Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2004)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  31. Nucci, L.: Education in the Moral Domain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2001)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  32. Pinker, S.: The Language Instinct. Morrow, New York (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Prinz, J.J.: The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Prinz, J.J. Is Morality Innate? In: Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.) Moral Psychology. Evolution of Morals, vol. 1. MIT Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Smetana, J.G.: Understanding of Social Rules. In: Bennett, M. (ed.) The Development of Social Cognition: The Child as Psychologist. Guilfort Press, New York (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Smetana, J.G.: Context, Conflict and Constraint in Adolescent-Parent Authority Relationships. In: Killen, M., Hart, D. (eds.) Morality in Everyday Life: Developmental Perspectives. Cambrigde University Press, Cambridge (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Smetana, J.G., Rote, W.M., Jambon, M., Tasopoulos-Chan, M., Villalobos, M., Comer, J.: Developmental Changes and Individual Differences in Young Children's moral Judgments. Child Dev. 84, 683–696 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  38. Thagard, P.: Mind. Introduction to Cognitive Science. MIT Press, Cambridge (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  39. Tisak, M.: Domains of Social Reasoning and Beyond. In: Vasta, R. (ed.) Annals of Child Development, vol. 11. Jessica Kingsley, London (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  40. Turiel, E.: The Development of Social Knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Turiel, E.: The Culture of Morality. Social Development, Context and Conict. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Turiel, E., Killen, M., Helwig, C.: Morality: Its Structure, Functions, and Vagaries. In: Kagan, J., Lamb, S. (eds.) The Emergence of Morality in Young Children. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1987)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sara Dellantonio .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this paper

Cite this paper

Dellantonio, S., Pastore, L. (2014). Freedom and Moral Judgment A Cognitive Model of Permissibility. In: Magnani, L. (eds) Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 8. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-37428-9_19

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics