Skip to main content

A Test of the Marginalist Defense of the Rational Voter Hypothesis Using Quantile Regression

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1417 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter uses quantile regression to uncover variations in the strength of the relationship between the expected closeness of the outcome, size of the electorate and voter turnout in Norwegian school language referendums. Referendums with a low turnout show a weak positive effect of closeness and a strong negative effect of size, the opposite being true of referendums with a high turnout. The results substantiate the marginalist defense of the Downsian rational voter hypothesis, which asserts that, while closeness and size cannot explain the absolute level of turnout, they can account for change at the margin.

An earlier version of this chapter has been published in HOMO OECONOMICUS 28(1/2): “Essays in Honor of Hannu Nurmi, Volume II,” edited by Manfred J. Holler, Andreas Nohn, and Hannu Vartiainen.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For comprehensive surveys of recent developments, see Koenker and Hallock (2001) and Koenker (2005).

  2. 2.

    Books by Brennan and Lomasky (1997), Brennan and Hamlin (2000) and Schuessler (2000) provide extensive accounts of expressive motivations in mass participation. The ethical voter hypothesis was initially proposed by Riker and Ordeshook (1968). A discussion of the importance of ethical motivations can be found in Blais (2000), who provides survey evidence in its favor.

  3. 3.

    See Downs (1957, Chaps. 11–14) and, for further developments, Tullock (1967, pp. 110–114) and Riker and Ordeshook (1968).

  4. 4.

    For an odd \(N\), the analogous probability is obtained by replacing \(N\) with \(N-1\) (Appendix).

  5. 5.

    See also Aldrich (1995, 1997) and Schachar and Nalebuff (1999).

  6. 6.

    This was the case from 01.07.1971 to 31.07.1985, and from 01.08.1999 to 31.07.2000.

References

  • Aldrich, J. H. (1995). Why parties? The origin and transformation of political parties in America. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich, J. H. (1997). When is it rational to vote? In D. C. Mueller (Ed.), Perspectives on public choice (pp. 373–390). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (1970). Sociologists, economists, and democracy. London: Collier Macmillan Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blais, A. (2000). To vote or not to vote: The merits and limits of rational choice theory. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G., & Hamlin, A. (2000). Democratic devices and desires. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G., & Lomasky, L. E. (1997). Democracy and decision. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chamberlain, G., & Rothschild, M. (1981). A note on the probability of casting a decisive vote. Journal of Economic Theory, 25, 152–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costa, D. L., & Kahn, M. E. (2003). Civic engagement and community heterogeneity: An economist’s perspective. Perspectives on Politics 1, 103–111. Unpublished manuscript, Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edlin, A., Gelman, A., & Kaplan, N. (2005). Voting as a rational choice: The effect of preferences regarding the well-being of others. Unpublished manuscript, University of California, Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T., & Pesendorfer, W. (1996). The swing voters curse. American Political Science Review, 86, 408–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I., & Mayer, L. (1975). Estimating the efficacy of a vote. Behavioral Science, 20, 25–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grofman, B. (1981). Fair apportionment and the Banzhaf index. The American Mathematical Monthly, 88, 1–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grofman, B. (1993). Is turnout the paradox that ate rational choice theory? In B. Grofman (Ed.), Perspectives on public choice (pp. 93–103). University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaniovski, S. (2008). The exact bias of the Banzhaf measure of power when votes are neither equiprobable nor independent. Social Choice and Welfare, 31, 281–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaniovski, S., & Mueller, D. C. (2006). Community size, heterogeneity and voter turnouts. Public Choice, 129, 399–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G., & Schimmelpfennig, J. (1992). Closeness counts if it matters for electoral victory: Some empirical results for the United Kingdom and the Federal Republic of Germany. Public Choice, 73, 283–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner, G., & Schulz, T. (2005). Expected closeness or mobilisation: Why do voters go to the polls?—empirical results for Switzerland, 1981–1999. Unpublished manuscript, University of St.Gallen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koenker, R. (2005). Quantile regression. New York: Econometric Society Monographs, Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koenker, R., & Bassett, G. W. (1978). Regression quantiles. Econometrica, 46, 30–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenker, R., & Hallock, K. F. (2001). Quantile regression. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 15, 143–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matsusaka, J. G., & Palda, F. (1993). The Downsian voter meets the ecological fallacy. Public Choice, 77, 855–878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mueller, D. C. (2003). Public choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H., & Ordeshook, P. C. (1968). A theory of the calculus of voting. American Political Science Review, 62, 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schachar, R., & Nalebuff, B. (1999). Follow the leader: Theory and evidence on political participation. American Economic Review, 89, 525–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schuessler, A. A. (2000). A logic of expressive choice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Søberg, M., & Tangerås, T. P. (2004). Rational voter turnout. Evidence from 232 Norwegian referendums. Unpublished manuscript, The Research Institute of Industrial Economics, Stockholm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1967). Towards a mathematics of politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Morten Søberg, who provided the data on Norwegian school language referendums, and Dennis C. Mueller for constructive criticism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Serguei Kaniovski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix Probability that a Vote is Decisive in a Two-Way Election

Appendix Probability that a Vote is Decisive in a Two-Way Election

When a voter faces two alternatives her vote becomes decisive either when all other votes would have tied the outcome (Event 1), or when her preferred alternative would lose by a single vote if she abstained (Event 2). The two events are mutually exclusive, as \(N\) is odd in the former case and even in the latter. Let \(p\) be a prior probability of a vote being cast for the voter’s preferred alternative. Event 1 occurs with probability \(P_o\), which is the probability of \(\frac{N-1}{2}\) successes in \(N-1\) Bernoulli trials with the probability of success \(p\):

$$\begin{aligned} P_o=\frac{(N-1)!}{(\frac{N-1}{2}!)^2}p^{\frac{N-1}{2}}(1-p)^{\frac{N-1}{2}}. \end{aligned}$$
(6)

Since \(N\) is odd, substitute \(N=2k+1\) for \(k=0,1,\dots \)

$$\begin{aligned} P_o=\frac{(2k)!}{(k!)^2}p^k(1-p)^k. \end{aligned}$$
(7)

By the Stirling’s approximation \(x!\cong \sqrt{2\pi }(x^{x+0.5}e^{-x})\), where \(\cong \) means that the ratio of the right hand side to the left hand side approaches unity as \(x\rightarrow \infty \),

$$\begin{aligned} P_o\cong \frac{\sqrt{2\pi }(2k)^{2k + 0.5}e^{-2k}}{(2\pi )(k^{k + 0.5}e^{-k})^2}p^k(1-p)^k=\frac{2^{2k + 0.5}}{\sqrt{2\pi k}}p^k(1-p)^k. \end{aligned}$$
(8)

Substituting back \(k=(N-1)/2\) yields, after some simplification,

$$\begin{aligned} P_o\approx \frac{2[1-(2p-1)^2]^{\frac{N-1}{2}}}{2\sqrt{\pi (N-1)}}. \end{aligned}$$
(9)

Note that in \([0,1]\) both \(x(1-x)\) and \(1-(2x-1)^2\) attain their maxima at \(x=0.5\), so that the approximation preserves \(P_o\)’s essential property of being highest at \(p=0.5\). Using the fact that \(1+x\approx e^x\) for small \(|x|\) and \(1-(2p-1)^2\approx e^{-(2p-1)^2}=e^{-4(p-0.5)^2}\), for all \(p\) close to 0.5 the above expression can written as

$$\begin{aligned} P_o\approx \frac{2e^{-2(N-1)(p-0.5)^2}}{\sqrt{2\pi (N-1)}}. \end{aligned}$$
(10)

This formula leads to the convenient log-linear specification with an interaction term between the quadratic measure of closeness \((p-0.5)^2\) and size \(N\).

Event 2 occurs with probability \(P_e\), which is the probability of \(\frac{N}{2}\) successes in \(N-1\) Bernoulli trials with the probability of success \(p\). By a similar argument using the parity of \(N\), for all \(p\) close to 0.5,

$$\begin{aligned} P_e\approx \frac{2e^{-2N(p-0.5)^2}}{\sqrt{2\pi N}}. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Good and Mayer (1975) discuss the magnitude of error in \(P_o\) and \(P_e\) due to \(p\) deviating from 0.5, which can be substantial (Fig. 2). See, also Chamberlain and Rothschild (1981), and in the context of voting power, Grofman (1981). Kaniovski (2008) computes the probability of casting a decisive vote when votes are neither equally probable to be for or against, nor independent. Departures from either assumption induce a substantial bias in this probability compared to the baseline case of equally probable and independent votes. The bias incurred by the probability deviating from one-half is larger than that incurred by the Pearson product-moment correlation coefficient deviating from zero.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Approximation to the probability of casting a decisive vote. In an election with two alternatives, the Probability of being decisive decreases with the size of electorate \(N\) and with \(|p-0.5|\). For a fixed \(N\), the probability is the highest when \(p=0.5\) and decreases rapidly as \(p\) deviates from 0.5. The approximation is valid for \(p\approx 0.5\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kaniovski, S. (2013). A Test of the Marginalist Defense of the Rational Voter Hypothesis Using Quantile Regression. In: Holler, M., Nurmi, H. (eds) Power, Voting, and Voting Power: 30 Years After. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-35929-3_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-35929-3_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-35928-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-35929-3

  • eBook Packages: Business and EconomicsEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics