Skip to main content

A Non-existence Theorem for Clientelism in Spatial Models

  • Chapter
Advances in Political Economy
  • 882 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter proposes a spatial model that combines both programmatic as well as clientelistic modes of vote-seeking. In the model political parties strategically choose: (1) their programmatic policy position, (2) the effort they devote to clientelism as opposed to the promotion of their programmatic position, and (3) the set of voters who are targeted to receive clientelistic benefits. I present a theorem which demonstrates that, in its most general form, a spatial model with clientelism yields either Downsian convergence without clientelist targeting, or an inifinite cycle. Put otherwise, in its most general form the model never yields a Nash Equilibrium with positive levels of clientelism. I relate this result to past research on instability in coalition formation processes, and then identify additional restrictions, regarding voter turnout and the set of voters which parties can target, which serve to generate Nash equilibria with positive clientelist effort.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A similar accountability mechanism underpins the ‘Responsible Party Government’ model, which dates at least to Lipset and Rokkan (1967), and sees ties between political parties and voters as grounded in campaign and governance strategies on issues of national-level public policy.

  2. 2.

    Competitiveness is a notably tricky concept to precisely define and operationalize. Different authors have assigned the concept different empirical referents. Kitschelt and Wilkinson (2007) define competitive elections as those in which “…elections are close between rival blocs of parties… and there is a market of uncommitted voters sufficiently large to tip the balance in favor of one or another bloc.” (p. 28)

  3. 3.

    However they also note that it is not patron-client ties themselves that generate less than ideal fiscal policy, but rather national officials’ lack of credibility. Indeed, in a world without such credibility the presence of local patrons actually improves voter welfare as compared to one without such local intermediaries.

  4. 4.

    These extremes, however, are unlikely to be observed in the empirical world, where politicians tend to target more than a single citizen but less than the entire citizenry with clientelistic inducements.

  5. 5.

    Both assumptions are primarily technical, and simplify the model immensely. As well, both are plausible: it seems quite natural to eliminate the possibility of an electoral strategy in which parties attempt to include extremists from both sides of the political spectrum in their target set. That said, Assumptions 1 and 2 do eliminate from candidates’ action sets a series of campaign strategies which may, at least in theory, be observed empirically. In future iterations I will examine the consequences of relaxing both assumptions.

  6. 6.

    The purely office-seeking assumption is the simplest of all candidate preference models. More recent research has extended the traditional spatial model to situations in which candidates also care about the policies which are implemented as a result of democratic elections (e.g. Wittman 1983; Calvert 1985). Strom (1990) represents an early attempt to explain why some candidates might be primarily office- and/or vote-seeking while others might be primarily policy-seeking.

  7. 7.

    The functional form in (1) implies that voters’ programmatic utility for P will always be increasing in G P . In the current model, the dimension x P is a public good continuum; differing ideal points on x P represent distinct preferences as to the ideal nature of public goods. Some voters may prefer national security, some environmental protection, and others free access to social services. That said, voters benefit from increased public good provision even when the nature of the good provided is not their most-preferred. Voters who prefer national security to environmental protection will nonetheless, all else held constant, benefit from reduced pollution. Formal models of public good provision often assume that voters are risk averse; if we were to assume that higher levels of G P reduce the uncertainty surrounding parties’ ability to implement national-level policies, voters’ programmatic utility for P would again increase with G P . As a result, (2) captures the type of programmatic utility of interest to this paper.

  8. 8.

    Of course, empirically this is unlikely to be the case: voters within a given electorate will likely exhibit some degree of differentiation according to their socio-economic and cultural status.

  9. 9.

    The model may eventually be extended to situations in which δ is endogenously determined by the set of candidate campaign strategies and voter choices. For example, one might envision δ as assuming high values among moderate voters when both parties choose extremist policies in x i ∈[0,1]: the alienation which arises from political extremism may make moderates particularly susceptible to more ‘cynical’ electoral appeals.

  10. 10.

    Voters with ideal points will all have a higher programmatic utility for ∼P than for P since: (a) they are located closer to ∼P in policy space, and (b) G P =1>G P .

References

  • Calvert RL (1985) Robustness of the multi-dimensional voting model: candidate motivations, uncertainty, and convergence. Am J Polit Sci 29:69–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs A (1957) An economic theory of democracy. Harper and Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez M, Pierskalla J (2009) Partisan strategies and political economic performance. Do modes of democratic accountability affect economic fortunes? Paper presented at the 2009 annual meeting of the American political science association, Toronto, Canada, September 3rd–6th

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys M (2008) Coalitions. Annu Rev Pol Sci 11:351–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keefer P, Vlaicu R (2008) Credibility, clientelism and democracy. J Law Econ Organ 24(2):371–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitschelt H, Wilkinson S (2007) Citizen-politician linkages: an introduction. In: Kitschelt H, Wilkinson S (eds) Patrons, clients, and policies. Patterns of democratic accountability and political competition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kselman D (2008) Governance and intra-party choice. Economics masters thesis, Duke University Department of Economics

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipset SM, Rokkan S (eds) (1967) Party systems and voter alignments. A cross-national perspective. Free Press, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Magaloni B Diaz-Cayeros A et al. (2007) Clientelism and portfolio diversification: a model of electoral investment with applications to Mexico. In: Kitschelt H, Wilkinson S (eds) Patrons, clients, and policies. Patterns of democratic accountability and political competition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash JF (1953) Two-person cooperative games. Econometrica 21:128–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichter S (2008) Vote buying or turnout buying? Machine politics and the secret ballot. Am Polit Sci Rev 102(01):19–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson T, Tabellini G (2000) Political economics. Explaining economic policy. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes SC (2005) Perverse accountability: a formal model of machine politics with evidence from Argentina. Am Polit Sci Rev 99(03):315–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strom K (1990) A behavioral theory of competitive political parties. Am J Polit Sci 34:565–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittman D (1983) Candidate motivations: a synthesis of alternative theories. Am Polit Sci Rev 77:142–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Kselman .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Theoretical Appendix

Theoretical Appendix

1.1 6.1 Proof of Lemma 2 for the Case

If and P’s opponent ∼P chooses v m , it will be impossible to for P to persuade any voters on programmatic grounds. To see this note that, when , no voter will have a purely programmatic utility for P greater than (i.e. for all voters). As well, note that all voters have a programmatic utility of at least for any candidate ∼P who chooses v m : the voters least satisfied with this platform are those with ideal points x i =1 and x i =0, and for these voters for any party ∼P which chooses the median voter programmatic vector v m .

As a result, when and P’s opponent ∼P chooses v m ,P will only gain the support of voters who are in its target set. In turn, any deviation from the outcome v 1=v 2=v m will need to involve a target set of at least half the electorate in order to give P a chance of winning. Furthermore, any target set greater than a bare plurality contains more voters than necessary to win the election, and thus will not represent the necessary condition choices \(\underline{\hat{x}}_{P}(G_{P})\), and \(\hat{\overline{x}}_{P}(G_{P})\) (recall above definition of necessity).

By Assumption 1 above, this bare plurality target set will include the median voter. The median voter will be the voter from this target set whose allegiance will be most difficult to gain, since the opposing party ∼P chooses the median voter’s ideal point at v m . It follows that \(\hat{x}_{P}(G_{P}) = x_{m}\).

1.2 6.2 Lemma 3 and the Ideological Swing Voter

When and P’s opponent ∼P chooses v m , it may be possible to for P to persuade some voters on programmatic grounds. In turn, there may exist payoff-enhancing deviations for P which do not involve choosing a bare plurality target set. Lemma 3 establishes the necessary condition strategy for a payoff-enhancing deviation which does not involve a bare plurality target set. Put otherwise, if the strategy identified in Lemma 3 leads does not lead to , then no deviation without a bare plurality target set is payoff-enhancing. Lemma 3 establishes the necessary condition strategy for a payoff-enhancing deviation on the political right; a symmetric condition applies on the political right.

Lemma 3

For any , the necessary condition strategy without a bare plurality target set on the political right is and .

This lemma, tells us that for any the necessary condition strategy for payoff-enhancing deviation on the political right involves the platform and the target set . For example, if G P =.8 then \(\hat{x}_{P}(.8) = .7\) and the C P =.2 units of clientelistic effort will be targeted to voters in the range \(\hat{\varTheta } _{P} = [.5,.7]\).

Proof of Lemma 3

When one party ∼P chooses the median-voter programmatic strategy vector v m and her opponent P chooses x P and , define x S as the swing ideological voter, a voter whose programmatic utility for party P is the same as his or her programmatic for party ∼P:

$$ u_{S,P}(\mathrm{prog}) = u_{S,\sim P}(\mathrm{prog})\quad \Rightarrow\quad G_{P} \cdot\bigl(1 - abs[x_{P} - x_{S}]\bigr) = 1 - abs[x_{m} - x_{S}]. $$
(A.1)

We will now identify, for any , the swing ideological voter x S when ∼P chooses v m and P chooses , i.e. when P chooses an ideological deviation on the political right. An identical process applies for deviations on the political left. Note first that swing ideological voters may exist both in the range and in the range [x P ,1], i.e. both voters to the left and to the right of x P may be indifferent between the parties’ respective programmatic stances.Footnote 10

Define \(\underline{x}_{S}\) as a swing ideological voter in the range . Given our specification of programmatic utility u i,P (prog), for any the following expression implicitly defines \(\underline{x}_{S}\) when ∼P chooses v m and P chooses :

(A.2)

This can be rewritten as:

(A.3)

Based on (A.3) I establish the following Sub-lemma:

Sub-lemma 1

For any , whenP chooses v m and P chooses , there is no swing voter ideological voter \(\underline{x}_{S}\) in the range for values of .

Proof of Sub-lemma 1

We are looking for swing ideological voters in the range . As such, if (A.3) generates a value \(\underline{x}_{S} > x_{P}\), then there is no swing ideological voter \(\underline{x}_{S}\) in the range . To see this, note that (A.2) above applies only to voters in the range . In turn, if (A.3) generates a value \(\underline{x}_{S} > x_{P}\), we know that the indifference conditions for a swing voter in the range are not satisfied for voters in the applicable range, such that there is no swing voter ideological voter \(\underline{x}_{S}\) in the range . It is then straightforward to establish that (algebra omitted), for any :

 □

In turn, for any Sub-lemma 1 allows to express \(\underline{x}_{S}\) as follows:

(A.4)

We now move to identifying ideological swing voters \(\overline{x}_{S}\) in the range [x P ,1]. Given our specification of programmatic utility u i,P (prog), for any the following expression implicitly defines \(\overline{x}_{S}\) when ∼P chooses v m and P chooses :

(A.5)

This can be rewritten as:

(A.6)

Based on (A.6) we can establish the following Sub-lemmas:

Sub-lemma 2

For any , whenP chooses v m and P chooses , there is no swing voter ideological voter \(\overline{x}_{S}\) in the range [x P ,1] for values of .

Sub-lemma 3

For any , whenP chooses v m and P chooses , there is no swing voter ideological voter \(\overline{x}_{S}\) in the range [x P ,1] for values of .

Proof of Sub-lemma 2

We are looking for swing ideological voters in the range [x P ,1]. By definition, if (A.6) generates a value \(\overline{x}_{S} > 1\), then there is no swing ideological voter \(\overline{x}_{S}\) in the range [x P ,1]: no voters in the applicable range satisfy the indifference condition in (A.6). It is then straightforward to establish that (algebra omitted):

 □

Proof of Sub-lemma 3

We are looking for swing ideological voters in the range [x P ,1]. By definition, if (A.6) generates a value \(\overline{x}_{S} < x_{P}\), then there is no swing ideological voter \(\overline{x}_{S}\) in the range [x P ,1]: no voters in the applicable range satisfy the indifference condition in (A.6). It is then straightforward to establish that (algebra omitted),

 □

Sub-lemmas 2 and 3 allow us to express \(\overline{x}_{S}\) as follows:

(A.7)

Taken together, expressions (A.4) and (A.7) tell us that, for any , when ∼P chooses v m and P chooses the game never has more than one swing voter, i.e. the existence conditions stipulated in Sub-lemmas 1, 2, and 3 are never simultaneously satisfied for both \(\underline{x}_{S}\) and \(\overline{x}_{S}\). Furthermore, they allow us to precisely identify the swing ideological voter for any and :

(A.8)

In words, when the game has no swing ideological voters. At such moderate values of x P , all voters have a higher programmatic utility for party ∼P than for partyP, because the latter has not sufficiently distinguished her programmatic stance from the median voter policy adopted by ∼P. In contrast, at intermediate values of the game’s swing ideological voter will be \(\overline{x}_{S} \in[x_{P},1]\), and the subset of extremist voters in the range \([\overline{x}_{S},1]\) will have a higher programmatic utility for P than for ∼P despite the fact that G P =1>G P . Finally, at more extreme values of , the game’s swing ideological voter will be , and all voters in the range \([\underline{x}_{S},1]\) will have a higher programmatic utility for P than for ∼P despite the fact that G P =1>G P .

Note from the above swing voter analysis that, for any value of , voters with ideal points in the range [x S ,1] have a higher programmatic utility for party P than for party ∼P. It follows immediately from (A.8) that, for any , the programmatic position is the position which maximizes the range of [x S ,1], i.e. maximizes the number of voters who prefer P on purely programmatic grounds. For any and , P will only target clientelistic goods to some subset of voters with ideal points x i <x S , since those with ideal points x i >x S can be counted on to choose P on purely programmatic grounds. It follows that the necessary condition strategy given some includes the platform : this is the policy position which maximizes the number of P’s ideological supporters, and in turn minimizes the size of Θ P to which P’s clientelistic efforts will need to be targeted so as to secure a bare majority.

When P chooses , it is straightforward to see from (A.8) above that the game’s swing ideological voter has ideal point , i.e. that the swing ideological voter is the voter whose ideal point is identical to P’s programmatic position. All voters with ideal points prefer ∼P to P on purely programmatic grounds, and vice versa for voters with ideal points . In turn, given that we know that , i.e. that target set most conducive to securing a bare majority victory, is that which targets all voters between the median ideal point and the swing voter . □

1.3 6.3 Proof of Lemma 2 for the Case

The median voter receives a utility of ‘1’ from the set of actions v m . On the other hand, Lemma 2 tells us that, when η=1, the median voter’s utility for necessary condition deviations when will be:

(A.9)

When , party P can consider both locally optimal deviations with a bare majority is target set and the median policy stance (Lemma 2), or deviations to the political right or left (Lemma 3). If the former, the median voter’s utility when η=1 will be (A.9). If the latter, the median voter’s utility for locally optimal deviations when η=1 will be:

$$ u_{m,P}\bigl(\hat{x}(G_{P},),\hat{\varTheta } _{P}(G_{P})\bigr) = (G_{P})^{2} + \biggl( \frac{1 - G_{P}}{\delta+ 1 - G_{P}} \biggr) . $$
(A.10)

To prove Lemma 2, I first establish that, for any , the median voter will always receive a higher utility from the deviation stipulated in Lemma 2 than that stipulated in Lemma 3: (A.9) > (A.10) (algebra omitted). This in turn implies that the strategy identified Lemma 2 is more likely to yield payoff-enhancing deviations than is that identified in Lemma 3, i.e. if the strategy from Lemma 2 yields a payoff-enhancing deviation then so does the strategy in Lemma 3, but not vice versa. This establishes Lemma 2 in the text, i.e. that for any value of G P <1 Lemma 2 identifies the necessary condition strategy for payoff-enhancing deviations.

1.4 6.4 Proof of Proposition 1

When η=1, as long as there does not exist a payoff-improving deviation from v m to a value G P <1, and conversely as long there does exist a payoff-improving deviation from v m to a value G P <1.

Given a deviation from v m to the necessary condition strategy, it is straightforward to see that, as long as the median voter prefers the deviating candidate P to the her opponent ∼P, then do all other voters in P’s target set. The median voter receives a utility of ‘1’ from the set of actions v m . On the other hand, when η=1, the median voter’s utility for the necessary condition strategy when G P <1 will be:

(A.11)

In turn it is straightforward to see that, for values of G P <1, the function can only be greater than ‘1’ if (algebra omitted).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kselman, D. (2013). A Non-existence Theorem for Clientelism in Spatial Models. In: Schofield, N., Caballero, G., Kselman, D. (eds) Advances in Political Economy. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-35239-3_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics