Skip to main content

The Relevance of Organizational Knowledge

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Organizational Epistemology

Part of the book series: Contributions to Management Science ((MANAGEMENT SC.))

  • 1553 Accesses

Abstract

Before exploring how organizational knowledge is applied (Chap. 3) and created (Chap. 4) we will develop a general view on organizational knowledge as grounding of organizational concepts. Hereby, we are going to outline a “strong view” which makes knowledge the basis for human action. As such its central relevance is given in all social fields, including of course organizations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Author’s translation; original citation: “Wahrnehmungs- und Gliederungsprinzipien”

  2. 2.

    In fact, Bourdieu’s notion of “habitus” connects society and individuals (Knoblauch, 2003). The interdependence between subjective and objective, between social field and habitus, or between structure and construction, forms a “structuralist constructivism [strukturalistischer Konstruktivismus]” (Bourdieu, 1992, p. 155) which is very similar to Giddens “structuration”. The inner relation between the theories of Giddens and Bourdieu (and to that of Actor-Network-Theory which will play a crucial role in Chap. 4) is also claimed by John Law (1992, p. 386).

  3. 3.

    Inspired by (Hatch & Cunliffe, 2006, p. 123ff.)

  4. 4.

    Of course this says nothing about success or failure of the new distinctions. Say, the CRM would allow only a very inflexible prioritization of customers leading to dysfunctional effects and non-acceptability by the sales persons. The system then would be too “rigid” and not adaptable to the flexible context of its application. These drawbacks would be challenged with new distinctions: if the system is too inflexible (but still has to stay in place) presumably new distinctions will be developed and informal “workarounds” developed. This may in a longer term evolve to new formal procedures, e.g. to an updated version of the CRM system.

  5. 5.

    See—among many others—(Boisot, 1995; Nonaka & Takeuchi, 1995; Probst, Raub, & Romhardt, 2002)

  6. 6.

    This example is inspired by students of the class “Elektronisch gestütztes Lern- und Wissensmanagement” supervised at the Vienna University of Economic and Business Administration in winter term 2008.

  7. 7.

    The concept goes back to Aristotle’s “On Interpretation” (Aristotle, 1984) and was further developed by the pragmatist tradition, e.g. by Charles W. Morris (1946) or Charles Sanders Peirce (1913).

  8. 8.

    Saussure expresses the relation between syntactic and semantic level via the notions of “signifier” vs. “signified” (Saussure, 1959). A similar distinction has been proposed by Charles S. Pierce who distinguishes between “representamen” and “interpretant” (Peirce, 1913).

  9. 9.

    My proposed structure actually does not take the problem of objective reference into account. Peirce recognized this additional dimension and called it the “object” vs. the mere “interpretant” – i.e. the object vs. its meaning. For Peirce the “object” marks the entity to which an “interpretant” refers (Peirce, 1897/1932). Note that what we call “concept” is not such an “object”, but much more the integrative relation of correlating representation (syntactic), meaning (semantic) and practice (pragmatic). My account therefore is more similar to Saussures dyadic approach which subsumes “sign” as the unification of “signifier” (as the linguistic form a sign takes) and “signified” (as the meaning, or “idea”, the signifier refers to). Whether that idea is related to an object, i.e. claiming ontological status or even truth, is not relevant to Saussure’s sign theory. The only thing that may claim some sort of ontological status is the signifier: written or spoken words have to exist in order to be interpreted (Saussure, 1959). However, our account extends Saussure’s as we add the pragmatic dimension which was later emphasized by Ludwig Wittgenstein (1953/2006).

  10. 10.

    The challenge for organizational studies then, of course, is how to understand and conceptualize organizational knowledge on all three levels, which is also one aim of our inquiry.

  11. 11.

    But notice that although pragmatical distinctions relate knowledge to action, knowledge does not equal action. Knowledge does not determine its real-world application to concrete organizational practice. Hence, organizational knowledge provides the possibility, not the necessity, for actors to construct specific representations, meanings, and actions in their organizational practice. Instead to support a “too strong” sense of knowledge where simply “knowledge is action” we will rather position knowledge as concept with a distance to its concrete application to practice: knowledge is related to action, it not is action (see next Sect. 2.2.4).

  12. 12.

    Another noteworthy position is held by Sybille Krämer who emphasize the material and representational dimension of human mind and thinking (Krämer, 2008, forthcoming 2011). See also the position of Klaus Krippendorff who highlights “meaning” as intersubjective “distinction-making” within the domain of (also organizational) design (Krippendorf, 1984, 1989, 2011; Krippendorf & Butter, 2007).

  13. 13.

    This integrative systematization is very much inspired by JC Spenders distinction of “knowledge-as-data”, “knowledge-as-meaning” and “knowing-as-practice” (Spender, 2008)

  14. 14.

    The distinction between “know-that” and “know-how” was introduced by the philosopher Gilbert Ryle (1949), that between explicit and tacit knowledge by Michel Polanyi (1967).

  15. 15.

    Which is the prototype of the “socialization” conversion (Nonaka et al., 2008, p. 20).

  16. 16.

    Designing knowledge management systems can be rather “technological oriented”, i.e. optimized towards creation and retrieval of knowledge itself, or “human oriented”, i.e. optimized towards creation and retrieval of knowledge holders (Maier & Hädrich, 2001).

  17. 17.

    See also our use-case from Seven-Eleven Japan in Chap. 10.

  18. 18.

    And consequently of course also aims at making the product better.

  19. 19.

    System theory approaches of organizational research drive this even further. According to an “autopoietic” understanding of organizations, members of the organization are placed to the “environment” of the system (i.e. humans are not “part” of the organization but part of the “environment” of the organization). Members become interchangeable and only relevant insofar as their communications and actions are “coupled” to the organizations processes (Simon, 2007, p. 35). The organization then does not consist of its members but of its own operations: organizations are “closed systems” (Baecker, 1998; Luhmann, 1995; Simon, 2007).

  20. 20.

    Having said that, we should also accept the limits of the introduced strong sense of organizational knowledge. Although the crucial importance of knowledge in organization forms both the assumption and the field of this inquiry, we should remember that not all before mentioned concepts, which create the organization (see Chap. 1), can (or should) be covered by and traced back to organizational knowledge. Our inquiry will not opt for some kind of knowledge-centrism which reduces everything in and around organizations to knowledge. I would not even choose to explain, e.g. expert skills or organizational rules by the concept of knowledge alone as other factors like social pressure, power, or culture may be involved as well. However, knowledge in the strong sense is a necessary condition for organizations. Trading off limits against importance of a knowledge-based view, we could conclude that on one hand knowledge for sure is not the only constituent of organizations, but on the other hand no organization would be imaginable without it. This is because no social field is imaginable without its epistemological grounding.

References

  • Aristotele. (1984). De Interpretatione (On interpretation). In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (Vol. 1). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baecker, D. (1998). Zum Problem des Wissens in Organisationen. OrganisationsEntwicklung, (3), 4–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, P. L., & Luckmann, T. (1969). Die gesellschaftliche Konstruktion der Wirklichkeit: Eine Theorie der Wissenssoziologie. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackler, F. (1995). Knowledge, knowledge work and organizations: An overview and interpretation. Organization Studies, 16(6), 1021–1046.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boisot, M. H. (1995). Information space - A framework for learning in organizations, institutions and culture (1. publ. ed.). London [u.a.]: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1986). Distinction: A social critique of the judgement of taste. London [u.a.]: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1992). Sozialer Raum und symbolische Macht. In P. Bourdieu (Ed.), Rede und Antwort (pp. 135–154). Frankfurt a.M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1998). Praktische Vernunft: Zur Theorie des Handelns (1. Aufl., dt. Erstausg. ed. Vol. 1985 = N.F.,985). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, D. (2007). Semiotics: The basics. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choo, C. W., & Bontis, N. (2002). The strategic management of intellectual capital and organizational knowledge. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drucker, P. F. (1993). Die postkapitalistische Gesellschaft. Düsseldorf/Wien [u.a.]: Econ-Verl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. (2008). The constitution of society: Outline of the theory of structuration (1. paperb. ed., reprint. ed.). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamel, G. (2002). Leading the revolution: How to thrive in turbulent times by making innovation a way of life. New York [u.a.]: Plume (1. Plume print. ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamel, G. (2007). The future of management. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatch, M. J., & Cunliffe, A. L. (2006). Organization theory: Modern, symbolic, and postmodern perspectives (2nd ed.). Oxford [u.a.]: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, R. M., & Clark, K. B. (1990). Architectural innovation – the reconfiguration of existing product technologies and the failure of established firms. Administrative Science Quarterly, 35(1), 9–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knoblauch, H. (2003). Habitus und Habitualisierung – Zur Komplementarität von Bourdieu mit dem Sozialkonstruktivismus. In B. Rehbein, G. Saalmann, & H. Schwengel (Eds.), Pierre Bourdieus Theorie des Sozialen. Probleme und Perspektiven. Konstanz: UVK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krämer, S. (2008). Medium, Bote, Übertragung: kleine Metaphysik der Medialität (1st ed.). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krämer, S. (forthcoming 2011). Punkt, Strich, Fläche. Über die Erkenntniskraft der Linie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krippendorf, K. (1984). An epistemological foundation for communication. Journal of Communication, 34(3), 21–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krippendorf, K. (1989). On the essential contexts of artifacts or on the proposition that “design is making sense (of things)”. Design Issues, 5(2), 9–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krippendorf, K. (2011). Principles of design and a trajectory of artificiality. Journal of Product Innovation Management, 28, 411–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krippendorf, K., & Butter, R. (2007). Semantics. Meanings and contexts of artifacts. In H. N. J. Schifferstein & P. Hekkert (Eds.), Product experience (pp. 1–25). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, J. (1992). Notes on the theory of the actor-network: Ordering, strategy, and heterogeneity. Systemic Practice and Action Research, 5(4), 379–393. doi:10.1007/BF01059830.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (1995). Funktionen und Folgen formaler Organisation: Mit einem Epilog 1994 (4th ed., Vol. 20). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, R., & Hädrich, T. (2001). Modell für die Erfolgsmessung von Wissensmanagementsystemen. Wirtschaftsinformatik, 43(5), 497–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1987). The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding (1st ed.). Boston: New Science Library: Distributed in the United State by Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, C. W. (1946). Signs, language and behavior. New York: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nonaka, I. (1991). Managing the firm as an information creation process. In J. R. Meindl, R. L. Cardy, & S. M. Puffer (Eds.), Advances in information processing in organizations (pp. 239–275). London: JAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nonaka, I., & Takeuchi, H. (1995). The knowledge-creating company: How Japanese companies create the dynamics of innovation. New York [u.a.]: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nonaka, I., Toyama, R., & Hirata, T. (2008). Managing flow: A process theory of the knowledge-based firm. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patriotta, G. (2003). Organizational knowledge in the making: How firms create, use and institutionalize knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press (1. publ. ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1897/1932). Division of signs. In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.), Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Vol. II, pp. 134–155). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1913). A syllabus of certain topics of logic. In N. Houser (Ed.), The essential Peirce. Selected philosophical writings (EP 2) (Vol. 2). Bloomington, IN [u.a.]: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, E. T. (1959). The theory of the growth of the firm. Oxford [u.a.]: Blackwell (1. print. ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1967). The tacit dimension. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Probst, G., Raub, S., & Romhardt, K. (2002). Managing knowledge: Building blocks for success. Chichester: Wiley (Reprinted ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London [u.a.]: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saussure, F. d. (1959). Course in general linguistics. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharmer, C. O. (2009). Theory U: Leading from the future as it emerges. The social technology of presencing. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schreyögg, G., & Geiger, D. (1997). The significance of distinctiveness: A proposal for rethinking organizational knowledge. Organization, 14(1), 77–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, F. B. (2007). Einführung in die systemische Organisationstheorie (1st ed.). Heidelberg: Carl-Auer-Verl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spender, J.-C. (2008). Organizational learning and knowledge management: Whence and whither? Management Learning, 39(2), 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas, H., & Vladimirou, E. (2001). What is organizational knowledge? Journal of Management Studies, 38(7), 973–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walgenbach, P. (2006). Giddens Theorie der Strukturierung. In A. Kieser (Ed.), Organisationstheorien (pp. 355–376). Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953/2006). Philosophical investigations: The German text, with revised English translation (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans. 5. ed., [50th anniversary commemorative ed.] ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Seirafi, K. (2013). The Relevance of Organizational Knowledge. In: Organizational Epistemology. Contributions to Management Science. Physica, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-34194-6_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics